In this book, Jean De Groot (hereafter D) engages in a single-minded defence of a particular thesis about Aristotle's empiricism. Instead of focusing on his study of animals (D is not as sensitive as some would now be to the anachronism of calling this his "biology"), she concentrates on the use of mechanical notions, especially what she dubs the "moving radius principle." This expresses the idea that the speeds with which points on a circumference move vary directly with the length of the radius of the circle in question, where she correctly notes that it was more awkward to speak about this in fourth-century B.C.E. Greek since there was no single term for "radius," only various locutions such as "the [straight] line drawn from the centre." One surprising feature of her discussion is that although the moving radius principle applies to any circular motion, she sometimes speaks of it as one of the movements into which, in the concentric spheres models of Eudoxus, Callippus, and Aristotle, planetary motion is resolved.The book maintains that - despite some recent studies of which I would rate Sylvia Berryman's 2009 monograph, The Mechanical Hypothesis in Ancient Greek Philosophy , the most important - mechanical notions have been unjustly neglected both by Aristotelian scholars and by historians of Greek science, although D is careful to distinguish ancient Greek views from those associated with the "mechanical philosophy" of the seventeenth century. In the process, D attacks some views that are, to be sure, grossly exaggerated, straw men in other words. One is the idea that Aristotle "read physical principles off the surface of things" (p. 15), and a second, the view that would reduce his philosophy of nature to a "philosophy of common opinions about nature" (p. 15), i.e., that it is "dialectic" or "endoxic" in character, rather than adopting a "scientific attitude" to the subject, that is one that we can recognise as such.For this enterprise, D draws heavily on the Problemata and the Mechanica , works generally thought not to be by Aristotle himself but probably emanating from his circle. This is a legitimate procedure, she claims, for two main reasons. First, there is enough evidence in the admittedly genuine works (e.g. On the Generation of Animals II 1 and 5, and Movement of Animals 1 and 7) for Aristotle's interest in mechanical ideas, so we should be allowed to supplement this with material from more doubtfully authentic works. Second, "even the works accepted as Aristotle's own are, as far as we know, notes of his lectures written by his students, or by Aristotle himself and then rewritten or reorganized by others" (p. …