79 results on '"interval order"'
Search Results
2. A characterization of interval orders with semiorder dimension two.
- Author
-
Apke, Alexander and Schrader, Rainer
- Subjects
- *
PARTIALLY ordered sets - Abstract
Given a partial order Q , its semiorder dimension is the smallest number of semiorders whose intersection is Q. When we look at the class of partial orders of fixed semiorder dimension k , no characterization is known, even in the case k = 2. In this paper, we give a characterization of the class of interval orders with semiorder dimension two. It follows from our results that partial orders that are interval orders with semiorder dimension two can be recognized efficiently. As our characterization makes use of a certain substructure, we also discuss the possibility of a forbidden suborder characterization. We give a partial answer to this question by listing all forbidden suborders for a special case. We further transfer our characterization result to the class of interval graphs that induce orders with semiorder dimension two. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2021
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
3. Interval orders with two interval lengths.
- Author
-
Boyadzhiyska, Simona, Isaak, Garth, and Trenk, Ann N.
- Subjects
- *
POLYNOMIAL time algorithms , *PARTIALLY ordered sets - Abstract
A poset P = (X , ≺) has an interval representation if each x ∈ X can be assigned a real interval I x so that x ≺ y in P if and only if I x lies completely to the left of I y. Such orders are called interval orders. In this paper we give a surprisingly simple forbidden poset characterization of those posets that have an interval representation in which each interval length is either 0 or 1. In addition, for posets (X , ≺) with a weight of 1 or 2 assigned to each point, we characterize those that have an interval representation in which for each x ∈ X the length of the interval assigned to x equals the weight assigned to x. For both problems we can determine in polynomial time whether the desired interval representation is possible and in the affirmative case, produce such a representation. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2019
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
4. Interval orders, semiorders and ordered groups.
- Author
-
Pouzet, Maurice and Zaguia, Imed
- Subjects
- *
CLIFFORD algebras , *ORDERED groups , *DO-not-resuscitate orders - Abstract
Abstract We prove that the order of an ordered group is an interval order if and only if it is a semiorder. Next, we prove that every semiorder is isomorphic to a collection J of intervals of some totally ordered abelian group, these intervals being of the form [ x , x + α [ for some positive α. We describe ordered groups such that the ordering is a semiorder and we introduce threshold groups generalizing totally ordered groups. We show that the free group on finitely many generators and the Thompson group F can be equipped with a compatible semiorder which is not a weak order. On another hand, a group introduced by Clifford cannot. Highlights • The order of an ordered group is an interval order if and only if it is a semiorder. • Every semiorder is isomorphic to a set of intervals of the form [ x , x + α [ , α > 0. • Description of ordered groups whose order is a semiorder. • Introduction of threshold orders and treshold groups. • Role of the free group on finitely many generators and the Thompson group. • A compatible semiorder on a Clifford group is a weak order. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2019
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
5. The niche graphs of interval orders
- Author
-
Park Jeongmi and Sano Yoshio
- Subjects
competition graph ,niche graph ,semiorder ,interval order ,Mathematics ,QA1-939 - Abstract
The niche graph of a digraph D is the (simple undirected) graph which has the same vertex set as D and has an edge between two distinct vertices x and y if and only if N+D(x) ∩ N+D(y) ≠ ∅ or N−D(x) ∩ N−D(y) ≠ ∅, where N+D(x) (resp. N−D(x)) is the set of out-neighbors (resp. in-neighbors) of x in D. A digraph D = (V,A) is called a semiorder (or a unit interval order ) if there exist a real-valued function f : V → R on the set V and a positive real number δ ∈ R such that (x, y) ∈ A if and only if f(x) > f(y)+δ. A digraph D = (V,A) is called an interval order if there exists an assignment J of a closed real interval J(x) ⊂ R to each vertex x ∈ V such that (x, y) ∈ A if and only if min J(x) > max J(y). Kim and Roberts characterized the competition graphs of semiorders and interval orders in 2002, and Sano characterized the competition-common enemy graphs of semiorders and interval orders in 2010. In this note, we give characterizations of the niche graphs of semiorders and interval orders
- Published
- 2014
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
6. Numerical Representation of Binary Relations with Multiplicative Error Function: A General Case
- Author
-
Ozbay, Erkut Yusuf, Fandel, G., editor, Trockel, W., editor, Bardsley, P., editor, Aliprantis, C. D., editor, Kovenock, Dan, editor, Tangian, Andranik S., editor, and Gruber, Josef, editor
- Published
- 2002
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
7. Strict [formula omitted]-Ferrers properties.
- Author
-
Giarlotta, Alfio and Watson, Stephen
- Subjects
- *
OPTICAL fiber networks , *COMBINATORICS , *MATHEMATICAL analysis , *OPTICAL communications , *OPTICAL fibers - Abstract
The transitivity of a preference relation is a traditional tenet of rationality in economic theory. However, several weakenings of transitivity have proven to be extremely useful in applications, giving rise to the notions of interval orders and semiorders among others. Strict ( m , 1 ) -Ferrers properties go in this direction, classifying asymmetric preferences on the basis of their degree of transitivity, which becomes generally weaker as m gets larger. We show that strict ( m , 1 ) -Ferrers properties can be arranged into a poset contained in the reverse ordering of the natural numbers. Our main result completely describes this poset. Although this paper has a combinatorial flavor, the topic of Ferrers properties is suited to applications in economics and psychology, for instance in relation to money-pump phenomena. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2018
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
8. Minimal representation of semiorders with intervals of same length
- Author
-
Mitas, Jutta, Goos, Gerhard, editor, Hartmanis, Juris, editor, Bouchitté, Vincent, editor, and Morvan, Michel, editor
- Published
- 1994
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
9. Well-graded families of NaP-preferences.
- Author
-
Giarlotta, Alfio and Watson, Stephen
- Subjects
- *
COMPLETENESS theorem , *FINITE element method , *SET theory , *THEORY of self-knowledge , *COHERENCE (Philosophy) - Abstract
A NaP-preference (necessary and possible preference) is a pair of nested reflexive relations on a set such that the smaller is transitive, the larger is complete, and the two components jointly satisfy natural forms of mixed completeness and transitive coherence. A NaP-preference is normalized if its smaller component is a partial order. We show that normalized NaP-preferences on a finite set are well-graded in the sense of Doignon and Falmagne (1997). [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2017
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
10. Universal semiorders.
- Author
-
Giarlotta, Alfio and Watson, Stephen
- Subjects
- *
LEXICOGRAPHY , *ORDER statistics , *SHIFT operators (Operator theory) , *INTEGERS , *MATHEMATICAL mappings - Abstract
A Z -product is a modified lexicographic product of three total preorders such that the middle factor is the chain of integers equipped with a shift operator. A Z -line is a Z -product having two linear orders as its extreme factors. We show that an arbitrary semiorder embeds into a Z -product having the transitive closure as its first factor, and a sliced trace as its last factor. Sliced traces are modified forms of traces induced by suitable integer-valued maps, and their definition is reminiscent of constructions related to the Scott–Suppes representation of a semiorder. Further, we show that Z -lines are universal semiorders, in the sense that they are semiorders, and each semiorder embeds into a Z -line. As a corollary of this description, we derive the well known fact that the dimension of a strict semiorder is at most three. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2016
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
11. [formula omitted]-rationalizable choices.
- Author
-
Cantone, Domenico, Giarlotta, Alfio, Greco, Salvatore, and Watson, Stephen
- Subjects
- *
RATIONALIZATION (Psychology) , *CHOICE (Psychology) , *AXIOMS , *INTERVAL analysis , *MATHEMATICAL models of psychology - Abstract
Rationalizability has been a main topic in individual choice theory since the seminal paper of Samuelson (1938). The rationalization of a multi-valued choice is classically obtained by maximizing the binary relation of revealed preference, which is fully informative of the primitive choice as long as suitable axioms of choice consistency hold. In line with this tradition, we give a purely axiomatic treatment of the topic of choice rationalization. In fact, we introduce a new class of properties of choice coherence, called axioms of replacement consistency, which examine how the addition of an item to a menu may cause a substitution in the selected set. These axioms are used to uniformly characterize rationalizable choices such that their revealed preferences are quasi-transitive, Ferrers, semitransitive, and transitive. Further, regardless of rationalizability, we study the relationship of these new axioms with some classical properties of choice consistency, such as standard contraction, standard expansion, and WARP . To complete our analysis of the transitive structure of rationalizable choices, we examine the case of revealed preferences satisfying weak ( m , n ) -Ferrers properties in the sense of Giarlotta and Watson (2014). Originally introduced with the purpose of extending the notions of interval orders and semiorders, these Ferrers properties give a descriptive taxonomy of binary relations displaying a transitive strict preference but an intransitive indifference. Here we suggest a possible economic interpretation of weak ( m , n ) -Ferrers properties, showing that, in a suitable model of transactions, they provide a way of controlling phenomena of money-pump due to the presence of mixed cycles of preference/indifference. Finally, we define ( m , n ) -rationalizable choices as those having a weakly ( m , n ) -Ferrers revealed preference, and characterize these choices by means of additional axioms of replacement consistency. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2016
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
12. A Genesis of Interval Orders and Semiorders: Transitive NaP-preferences.
- Author
-
Giarlotta, Alfio
- Abstract
A NaP-preference (necessary and possible preference) on a set A is a pair ${\left(\succsim^{^{_N}}\!,\,\succsim^{^{_P}}\!\right)}$ of binary relations on A such that its necessary component ${\succsim^{^{_N}} \!\!}$ is a partial preorder, its possible component ${\succsim^{^{_P}} \!\!}$ is a completion of ${\succsim^{^{_N}} \!\!}$, and the two components jointly satisfy natural forms of mixed completeness and mixed transitivity. We study additional mixed transitivity properties of a NaP-preference ${\left(\succsim^{^{_N}}\!,\,\succsim^{^{_P}}\!\right)}$, which culminate in the full transitivity of its possible component ${\succsim^{^{_P}} \!\!}$. Interval orders and semiorders are strictly related to these properties, since they are the possible components of suitably transitive NaP-preferences. Further, we introduce strong versions of interval orders and semiorders, which are characterized by enhanced forms of mixed transitivity, and use a geometric approach to compare them to other well known preference relations. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2014
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
13. THE NICHE GRAPHS OF INTERVAL ORDERS.
- Author
-
JEONGMI PARK and YOSHIO SANO
- Subjects
- *
INTERVAL analysis , *GRAPH theory , *REAL numbers , *MATHEMATICAL functions , *DIRECTED graphs - Abstract
The niche graph of a digraph D is the (simple undirected) graph which has the same vertex set as D and has an edge between two distinct vertices x and y if and only if N+D (x) ∩ N+D (y) ≠ Ø or N-D (x) ∩ N-D (y) ≠ Ø, where N+D (x) (resp. N-D (x)) is the set of out-neighbors (resp. in-neighbors) of x in D. A digraph D = (V,A) is called a semiorder (or a unit interval order ) if there exist a real-valued function ƒ: V → ℝon the set V and a positive real number δ ∈ ℝ such that (x, y) ∈ A if and only if ƒ(x) > ƒ(y) + δ. A digraph D = (V,A) is called an interval order if there exists an assignment J of a closed real interval J(x) ⊂ ℝ to each vertex x ∈ V such that (x, y) ∈ A if and only if min J(x) > max J(y). Kim and Roberts characterized the competition graphs of semiorders and interval orders in 2002, and Sano characterized the competition-common enemy graphs of semiorders and interval orders in 2010. In this note, we give characterizations of the niche graphs of semiorders and interval orders. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2014
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
14. Hereditary Semiorders and Enumeration of Semiorders by Dimension
- Author
-
Stephen J. Young and Mitchel T. Keller
- Subjects
Applied Mathematics ,Dimension (graph theory) ,Semiorder ,Generating function ,Theoretical Computer Science ,Combinatorics ,Catalan number ,Computational Theory and Mathematics ,06A07, 05A15 ,Subsequence ,FOS: Mathematics ,Bijection ,Mathematics - Combinatorics ,Discrete Mathematics and Combinatorics ,Interval order ,Combinatorics (math.CO) ,Geometry and Topology ,Partially ordered set ,Mathematics - Abstract
In 2010, Bousquet-M\'elou et al. defined sequences of nonnegative integers called ascent sequences and showed that the ascent sequences of length $n$ are in one-to-one correspondence with the interval orders, i.e., the posets not containing the poset $\mathbf{2}+\mathbf{2}$. Through the use of generating functions, this provided an answer to the longstanding open question of enumerating the (unlabeled) interval orders. A semiorder is an interval order having a representation in which all intervals have the same length. In terms of forbidden subposets, the semiorders exclude $\mathbf{2}+\mathbf{2}$ and $\mathbf{1}+\mathbf{3}$. The number of unlabeled semiorders on $n$ points has long been known to be the $n$-th Catalan number. However, describing the ascent sequences that correspond to the semiorders under the bijection of Bousquet-M\'elou et al. has proved difficult. In this paper, we discuss a major part of the difficulty in this area: the ascent sequence corresponding to a semiorder may have an initial subsequence that corresponds to an interval order that is not a semiorder. We define the hereditary semiorders to be those corresponding to an ascent sequence for which every initial subsequence also corresponds to a semiorder. We provide a structural result that characterizes the hereditary semiorders and use this characterization to determine the ordinary generating function for hereditary semiorders. We also use our characterization of hereditary semiorders and the characterization of semiorders of dimension 3 given by Rabinovitch to provide a structural description of the semiorders of dimension at most 2. From this description, we are able to determine the ordinary generating for the semiorders of dimension at most 2., Comment: 27 pages, 19 figures, 1 table
- Published
- 2020
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
15. Bi-semiorders with frontiers on finite sets.
- Author
-
Bouyssou, Denis and Marchant, Thierry
- Subjects
- *
EXTENSIONS , *ORDER , *SET theory , *REPRESENTATION (Psychoanalysis) , *PARTITIONS (Mathematics) - Abstract
This paper studies an extension of bi-semiorders in which a “frontier” is added between the various relations used. This extension is motivated by the study of additive representations of ordered partitions and coverings defined on product sets of two components. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2015
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
16. Biorders with Frontier.
- Author
-
Bouyssou, Denis and Marchant, Thierry
- Subjects
SET theory ,MATHEMATICAL sequences ,MEASUREMENT ,MATHEMATICAL analysis ,MATHEMATICS ,ALGEBRA ,NUMERICAL analysis - Abstract
This paper studies an extension of biorders that has a 'frontier' between the relation and the absence of relation. This extension is motivated by a conjoint measurement problem consisting in the additive representation of ordered coverings defined on product sets of two components. We also investigate interval orders and semiorders with frontier. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2011
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
17. Inductive Characterizations of Finite Interval Orders and Semiorders.
- Author
-
Leblet, Jimmy and Rampon, Jean-Xavier
- Subjects
MATHEMATICAL proofs ,CARDINAL numbers ,PARTIALLY ordered sets ,SET theory ,RECURSIVE functions - Abstract
We introduce an inductive definition for two classes of orders. By simple proofs, we show that one corresponds to the interval orders class and that the other is exactly the semiorders class. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2009
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
18. Maximizing an interval order on compact subsets of its domain
- Author
-
Kukushkin, Nikolai S.
- Subjects
- *
AXIOM of choice , *AXIOMATIC set theory , *METRIC spaces , *SET theory - Abstract
Abstract: Maximal elements of a binary relation on compact subsets of a metric space define a choice function. An infinite extension of transitivity is necessary and sufficient for such a choice function to be nonempty-valued and path independent (or satisfy the outcast axiom). An infinite extension of acyclicity is necessary and sufficient for the choice function to have nonempty values provided the underlying relation is an interval order. [Copyright &y& Elsevier]
- Published
- 2008
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
19. AN ORDER-THEORETICAL EXTENSION OF THE GUTTMAN SCALE TO LESS SIMPLE ORDERS.
- Author
-
Hojo, Hiroshi
- Abstract
A perfect Guttman scale is rarely found in real data. Pairwise dominance relations between items to be scaled, however, often meet the conditions for less simple orders, such as strict partial orders, interval orders, and semiorders. Examples are thus provided for an extension of the Guttman scale to less simple orders in the framework of ordinal theory, or more specifically, the theory of representations with thresholds. The study is methodologically based on ordering theory. Three illustrative constructions of less simple orders demonstrate that they much more strongly account for real data than do Guttman scales, and that some uniqueness in scale values and thresholds is found in semiorders and interval orders. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2008
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
20. Homothetic interval orders
- Author
-
Lemaire, Bertrand and Le Menestrel, Marc
- Subjects
- *
SET theory , *MATHEMATICS , *LINEAR systems , *SYSTEMS theory - Abstract
Abstract: We give a characterization of the non-empty binary relations on a -set A such that there exist two morphisms of -sets verifying and . They are called homothetic interval orders. If is a homothetic interval order, we also give a representation of in terms of one morphism of -sets and a map such that . The pairs and are “uniquely” determined by , which allows us to recover one from each other. We prove that is a semiorder (resp. a weak order) if and only if is a constant map (resp. ). If moreover A is endowed with a structure of commutative semigroup, we give a characterization of the homothetic interval orders represented by a pair so that u is a morphism of semigroups. [Copyright &y& Elsevier]
- Published
- 2006
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
21. Well-graded families of NaP-preferences
- Author
-
Alfio Giarlotta and Stephen Watson
- Subjects
Discrete mathematics ,Transitive relation ,Well-graded family ,Partial order ,Semiorder ,Interval order ,NaP-preference ,Normalized NaP-preference ,Applied Mathematics ,05 social sciences ,050105 experimental psychology ,Combinatorics ,Set (abstract data type) ,Reflexive relation ,Completeness (order theory) ,0502 economics and business ,0501 psychology and cognitive sciences ,Finite set ,Preference (economics) ,General Psychology ,050205 econometrics ,Mathematics - Abstract
A NaP-preference (necessary and possible preference) is a pair of nested reflexive relations on a set such that the smaller is transitive, the larger is complete, and the two components jointly satisfy natural forms of mixed completeness and transitive coherence. A NaP-preference is normalized if its smaller component is a partial order. We show that normalized NaP-preferences on a finite set are well-graded in the sense of Doignon and Falmagne (1997).
- Published
- 2017
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
22. A representation for intransitive indifference relations
- Author
-
Özbay, Erkut Yusuf and Filiz, Emel
- Subjects
- *
NUMERICAL solutions to differential equations , *ERROR functions , *DEFINITE integrals , *PROBABILITY theory - Abstract
Abstract: Binary relations representable by utility functions with multiplicative error are considered. It is proved that if the error is a power of utility then the underlying binary relation is either an interval order, or a semiorder. Moreover, semiorders can be characterized among interval orders by the magnitude of the power of utility that is used in the form of error function. [Copyright &y& Elsevier]
- Published
- 2005
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
23. Interval orders, semiorders and ordered groups
- Author
-
Maurice Pouzet, Imed Zaguia, Institut Camille Jordan [Villeurbanne] (ICJ), École Centrale de Lyon (ECL), Université de Lyon-Université de Lyon-Université Claude Bernard Lyon 1 (UCBL), Université de Lyon-Université Jean Monnet [Saint-Étienne] (UJM)-Institut National des Sciences Appliquées de Lyon (INSA Lyon), Université de Lyon-Institut National des Sciences Appliquées (INSA)-Institut National des Sciences Appliquées (INSA)-Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique (CNRS), Combinatoire, théorie des nombres (CTN), Université de Lyon-Institut National des Sciences Appliquées (INSA)-Institut National des Sciences Appliquées (INSA)-Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique (CNRS)-École Centrale de Lyon (ECL), University of Calgary, and Collège militaire royal du Canada
- Subjects
Group (mathematics) ,Applied Mathematics ,010102 general mathematics ,05 social sciences ,Semiorder ,06A05, 06A06, 06F15, 06F20 ,[INFO.INFO-DM]Computer Science [cs]/Discrete Mathematics [cs.DM] ,01 natural sciences ,050105 experimental psychology ,Combinatorics ,Free group ,FOS: Mathematics ,Mathematics - Combinatorics ,Order (group theory) ,Interval (graph theory) ,0501 psychology and cognitive sciences ,Interval order ,Combinatorics (math.CO) ,0101 mathematics ,Abelian group ,General Psychology ,ComputingMilieux_MISCELLANEOUS ,Mathematics - Abstract
We prove that the order of an ordered group is an interval order if and only if it is a semiorder. Next, we prove that every semiorder is isomorphic to a collection $\mathcal J$ of intervals of some totally ordered abelian group, these intervals being of the form $[x, x+ \alpha[$ for some positive $\alpha$. We describe ordered groups such that the ordering is a semiorder and we introduce threshold groups generalizing totally ordered groups. We show that the free group on finitely many generators and the Thompson group $\mathbb F$ can be equipped with a compatible semiorder which is not a weak order. On another hand, a group introduced by Clifford cannot., Comment: 32 pages, 2 figures
- Published
- 2019
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
24. The pseudo-transitivity of preference relations: Strict and weak -Ferrers properties.
- Author
-
Giarlotta, Alfio and Watson, Stephen
- Subjects
- *
MATHEMATICAL models , *AXIOMS , *MATHEMATICAL symmetry , *BINARY number system , *GENERALIZATION , *SATISFACTION , *MONOTONIC functions - Abstract
Abstract: Traditionally, a preference on a set of alternatives is modeled by a binary relation on satisfying suitable axioms of pseudo-transitivity, such as the Ferrers condition ( and imply or ) or the semitransitivity property ( and imply or ). In this paper we study -Ferrers properties, which naturally generalize these axioms by requiring that and imply or . We identify two versions of -Ferrers properties: weak, related to a reflexive relation, and strict, related to its asymmetric part. We determine the relationship between these two versions of -Ferrers properties, which coincide whenever (i.e., for the classical Ferrers condition and for semitransitivity), otherwise displaying an almost dual behavior. In fact, as and increase, weak -Ferrers properties become stronger and stronger, whereas strict -Ferrers properties become somehow weaker and weaker (despite failing to display a monotonic behavior). We give a detailed description of the finite poset of weak -Ferrers properties, ordered by the relation of implication. This poset depicts a discrete evolution of the transitivity of a preference, starting from its absence and ending with its full satisfaction. [Copyright &y& Elsevier]
- Published
- 2014
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
25. (m,n)-rationalizable choices
- Author
-
Domenico Cantone, Salvatore Greco, Stephen Watson, and Alfio Giarlotta
- Subjects
Transitive relation ,Binary relation ,Applied Mathematics ,05 social sciences ,Semiorder ,Rationalizability ,Revealed preference ,0502 economics and business ,Interval order ,050207 economics ,Mathematical economics ,Social psychology ,General Psychology ,Axiom ,050205 econometrics ,Mathematics ,Economic interpretation - Abstract
Rationalizability has been a main topic in individual choice theory since the seminal paper of Samuelson (1938). The rationalization of a multi-valued choice is classically obtained by maximizing the binary relation of revealed preference, which is fully informative of the primitive choice as long as suitable axioms of choice consistency hold. In line with this tradition, we give a purely axiomatic treatment of the topic of choice rationalization. In fact, we introduce a new class of properties of choice coherence, called axioms of replacement consistency, which examine how the addition of an item to a menu may cause a substitution in the selected set. These axioms are used to uniformly characterize rationalizable choices such that their revealed preferences are quasi-transitive, Ferrers, semitransitive, and transitive. Further, regardless of rationalizability, we study the relationship of these new axioms with some classical properties of choice consistency, such as standard contraction, standard expansion, and WARP . To complete our analysis of the transitive structure of rationalizable choices, we examine the case of revealed preferences satisfying weak ( m , n ) -Ferrers properties in the sense of Giarlotta and Watson (2014). Originally introduced with the purpose of extending the notions of interval orders and semiorders, these Ferrers properties give a descriptive taxonomy of binary relations displaying a transitive strict preference but an intransitive indifference. Here we suggest a possible economic interpretation of weak ( m , n ) -Ferrers properties, showing that, in a suitable model of transactions, they provide a way of controlling phenomena of money-pump due to the presence of mixed cycles of preference/indifference. Finally, we define ( m , n ) -rationalizable choices as those having a weakly ( m , n ) -Ferrers revealed preference, and characterize these choices by means of additional axioms of replacement consistency.
- Published
- 2016
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
26. A selection of maximal elements under non-transitive indifferences
- Author
-
Alcantud, José Carlos R., Bosi, Gianni, and Zuanon, Magalì
- Subjects
- *
MULTIPLY transitive groups , *MAXIMAL subgroups , *MATHEMATICAL analysis , *ACYCLIC model , *MATHEMATICS - Abstract
Abstract: In this work we are concerned with maximality issues under intransitivity of the indifference. Our approach relies on the analysis of “undominated maximals” (cf., ). Provided that an agent’s binary relation is acyclic, this is a selection of its maximal elements that can always be done when the set of alternatives is finite. In the case of semiorders, proceeding in this way is the same as using Luce’s selected maximals. We present a sufficient condition for the existence of undominated maximals for interval orders without any cardinality restriction. Its application to certain types of continuous semiorders is very intuitive and accommodates the well-known “sugar example” by Luce. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2010
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
27. Strict (m,1)-Ferrers properties
- Author
-
Giarlotta, Alfio and Stephen, Watson
- Subjects
n)-Ferrers ,Money-pump ,Transitivity ,Semitransitivity ,Strict (m ,Weak (m ,Semiorder ,Interval order ,Ferrers property ,Ferrers stabilizer ,NaP-preference ,Weak (m, n)-Ferrers ,Strict (m, n)-Ferrers - Published
- 2018
28. A simple proof characterizing interval orders with interval lengths between 1 and $k$
- Author
-
Simona Boyadzhiyska, Garth Isaak, and Ann N. Trenk
- Subjects
interval graph ,General Mathematics ,010102 general mathematics ,Order (ring theory) ,Digraph ,0102 computer and information sciences ,01 natural sciences ,Combinatorics ,Integer ,interval order ,010201 computation theory & mathematics ,Simple (abstract algebra) ,FOS: Mathematics ,Interval (graph theory) ,Mathematics - Combinatorics ,Interval order ,Combinatorics (math.CO) ,semiorder ,05C62 ,0101 mathematics ,06A99, 05C62 ,Representation (mathematics) ,Partially ordered set ,06A99 ,Mathematics - Abstract
A poset $P= (X, \prec)$ has an interval representation if each $x \in X$ can be assigned a real interval $I_x$ so that $x \prec y$ in $P$ if and only if $I_x$ lies completely to the left of $I_y$. Such orders are called \emph{interval orders}. Fishburn proved that for any positive integer $k$, an interval order has a representation in which all interval lengths are between $1$ and $k$ if and only if the order does not contain $\mathbf{(k+2)+1}$ as an induced poset. In this paper, we give a simple proof of this result using a digraph model., Comment: 9 pages, 1 figure
- Published
- 2018
29. Biased extensive measurement: The general case
- Author
-
Le Menestrel, Marc and Lemaire, Bertrand
- Subjects
- *
FOUNDATIONS of geometry , *AXIOMS , *PHILOSOPHY of mathematics , *MATHEMATICS - Abstract
Abstract: We develop a theory of biased extensive measurement which allows us to prove the existence of a ratio-scale without transitivity of indifference and with a property of homothetic invariance weaker than independence. These representations, which cover the cases of interval orders and of semiorders, reveal a unique biasing function smaller or equal to 1 that distorts extensive measurement and explains departures from its standard axioms. We interpret this biasing function as characterizing the qualitative influence of the underlying measurement process and we show that it induces a proportional indifference threshold. [Copyright &y& Elsevier]
- Published
- 2006
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
30. Biased extensive measurement: The homogeneous case
- Author
-
Le Menestrel, Marc and Lemaire, Bertrand
- Subjects
- *
AXIOMS , *SYMMETRY (Physics) , *SCALING laws (Statistical physics) , *MONOTONIC functions - Abstract
In the homogeneous case of one type of objects, we prove the existence of an additive scale unique up to a positive scaling transformation without transitivity of indifference and with a property of homothetic invariance weaker than monotonicity. The representation, which is a particular case of a semiorder representation, reveals a unique positive factor
α⩽1 that biases extensive structures and explains departures from these standard axioms of extensive measurement(α=1) . We interpretα as characterizing the qualitative influence of the underlying measurement process and we show that it induces a proportional indifference threshold. [Copyright &y& Elsevier]- Published
- 2004
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
31. THE NICHE GRAPHS OF INTERVAL ORDERS
- Author
-
Yoshio Sano and Jeongmi Park
- Subjects
FOS: Computer and information sciences ,Discrete Mathematics (cs.DM) ,Applied Mathematics ,Semiorder ,Digraph ,Graph ,Vertex (geometry) ,Combinatorics ,competition graph ,interval order ,niche graph ,FOS: Mathematics ,QA1-939 ,Discrete Mathematics and Combinatorics ,Mathematics - Combinatorics ,05C75, 05C20, 06A06 ,Interval order ,Combinatorics (math.CO) ,semiorder ,Mathematics ,Real number ,Computer Science - Discrete Mathematics - Abstract
The niche graph of a digraph $D$ is the (simple undirected) graph which has the same vertex set as $D$ and has an edge between two distinct vertices $x$ and $y$ if and only if $N^+_D(x) \cap N^+_D(y) \neq \emptyset$ or $N^-_D(x) \cap N^-_D(y) \neq \emptyset$, where $N^+_D(x)$ (resp. $N^-_D(x)$) is the set of out-neighbors (resp. in-neighbors) of $x$ in $D$. A digraph $D=(V,A)$ is called a semiorder (or a unit interval order) if there exist a real-valued function $f:V \to \mathbb{R}$ on the set $V$ and a positive real number $\delta \in \mathbb{R}$ such that $(x,y) \in A$ if and only if $f(x) > f(y) + \delta$. A digraph $D=(V,A)$ is called an interval order if there exists an assignment $J$ of a closed real interval $J(x) \subset \mathbb{R}$ to each vertex $x \in V$ such that $(x,y) \in A$ if and only if $\min J(x) > \max J(y)$. S. -R. Kim and F. S. Roberts characterized the competition graphs of semiorders and interval orders in 2002, and Y. Sano characterized the competition-common enemy graphs of semiorders and interval orders in 2010. In this note, we give characterizations of the niche graphs of semiorders and interval orders., Comment: 7 pages
- Published
- 2014
32. The pseudo-transitivity of preference relations: Strict and weak -Ferrers properties
- Author
-
Stephen Watson and Alfio Giarlotta
- Subjects
Discrete mathematics ,Transitive relation ,Binary relation ,Applied Mathematics ,Semiorder ,Interval order ,Monotonic function ,Partially ordered set ,Preference (economics) ,General Psychology ,Axiom ,Mathematics - Abstract
Traditionally, a preference on a set A of alternatives is modeled by a binary relation R on A satisfying suitable axioms of pseudo-transitivity, such as the Ferrers condition ( a R b and c R d imply a R d or c R b ) or the semitransitivity property ( a R b and b R c imply a R d or d R c ). In this paper we study ( m , n ) -Ferrers properties, which naturally generalize these axioms by requiring that a 1 R … R a m and b 1 R … R b n imply a 1 R b n or b 1 R a m . We identify two versions of ( m , n ) -Ferrers properties: weak, related to a reflexive relation, and strict, related to its asymmetric part. We determine the relationship between these two versions of ( m , n ) -Ferrers properties, which coincide whenever m + n = 4 (i.e., for the classical Ferrers condition and for semitransitivity), otherwise displaying an almost dual behavior. In fact, as m and n increase, weak ( m , n ) -Ferrers properties become stronger and stronger, whereas strict ( m , n ) -Ferrers properties become somehow weaker and weaker (despite failing to display a monotonic behavior). We give a detailed description of the finite poset of weak ( m , n ) -Ferrers properties, ordered by the relation of implication. This poset depicts a discrete evolution of the transitivity of a preference, starting from its absence and ending with its full satisfaction.
- Published
- 2014
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
33. Universal Semiorders
- Author
-
Alfio Giarlotta and Stephen Watson
- Subjects
Applied Mathematics ,010102 general mathematics ,05 social sciences ,Semiorder ,Z-line ,Interval order ,01 natural sciences ,050105 experimental psychology ,Sliced trace ,Z-product ,Scott–Suppes representation ,0501 psychology and cognitive sciences ,0101 mathematics ,Trace ,General Psychology - Published
- 2016
34. (m,n)-rationalizable choices
- Author
-
Cantone, Domenico, Giarlotta, Alfio, Greco, Salvatore, and Watson, Stephen
- Subjects
Money-pump ,n)-Ferrers ,revealed preference ,(m,n)(m,n)-Ferrers ,Business and Management ,Semiorder ,Interval order ,individual choice ,rational choice ,axioms of choice consistency ,interval order ,semiorder ,total preorder ,(m,n)-Ferrers ,(m,n)-rationalizability ,money-pump ,Axioms of choice consistency ,Individual choice ,(m ,Rational choice ,Revealed preference ,(m,n)(m,n)-rationalizability ,Total preorder ,n)-rationalizability - Abstract
Rationalizability has been a main topic in individual choice theory since the seminal paper of Samuelson (1938). The rationalization of a multi-valued choice is classically obtained by maximizing the binary relation of revealed preference, which is fully informative of the primitive choice as long as suitable axioms of choice consistency hold. In line with this tradition, we give a purely axiomatic treatment of the topic of choice rationalization. In fact, we introduce a new class of properties of choice coherence, called axioms of replacement consistency, which examine how the addition of an item to a menu may cause a substitution in the selected set. These axioms are used to uniformly characterize rationalizable choices such that their revealed preferences are quasi-transitive, Ferrers, semitransitive, and transitive. Further, regardless of rationalizability, we study the relationship of these new axioms with some classical properties of choice consistency, such as standard contraction, standard expansion, and WARP. To complete our analysis of the transitive structure of rationalizable choices, we examine the case of revealed preferences satisfying weak (m,n)(m,n)-Ferrers properties in the sense of Giarlotta and Watson (2014). Originally introduced with the purpose of extending the notions of interval orders and semiorders, these Ferrers properties give a descriptive taxonomy of binary relations displaying a transitive strict preference but an intransitive indifference. Here we suggest a possible economic interpretation of weak (m,n)(m,n)-Ferrers properties, showing that, in a suitable model of transactions, they provide a way of controlling phenomena of money-pump due to the presence of mixed cycles of preference/indifference. Finally, we define (m,n)(m,n)-rationalizable choices as those having a weakly (m,n)(m,n)-Ferrers revealed preference, and characterize these choices by means of additional axioms of replacement consistency.
- Published
- 2016
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
35. Inductive Characterizations of Finite Interval Orders and Semiorders
- Author
-
Jimmy Leblet and Jean-Xavier Rampon
- Subjects
Discrete mathematics ,Class (set theory) ,Algebra and Number Theory ,Semiorder ,Mathematical proof ,Antichain ,Combinatorics ,Computational Theory and Mathematics ,Simple (abstract algebra) ,Interval (graph theory) ,Interval order ,Geometry and Topology ,Partially ordered set ,Mathematics - Abstract
We introduce an inductive definition for two classes of orders. By simple proofs, we show that one corresponds to the interval orders class and that the other is exactly the semiorders class.
- Published
- 2009
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
36. An Order-Theoretical Extension of the Guttman Scale to Less Simple Orders
- Author
-
Hiroshi Hojo
- Subjects
Discrete mathematics ,Scale (ratio) ,Applied Mathematics ,Semiorder ,Experimental and Cognitive Psychology ,Interval (mathematics) ,Guttman scale ,Clinical Psychology ,Simple (abstract algebra) ,Applied mathematics ,Pairwise comparison ,Interval order ,Uniqueness ,Analysis ,Mathematics - Abstract
A perfect Guttman scale is rarely found in real data. Pairwise dominance relations between items to be scaled, however, often meet the conditions for less simple orders, such as strict partial orders, interval orders, and semiorders. Examples are thus provided for an extension of the Guttman scale to less simple orders in the framework of ordinal theory, or more specifically, the theory of representations with thresholds. The study is methodologically based on ordering theory. Three illustrative constructions of less simple orders demonstrate that they much more strongly account for real data than do Guttman scales, and that some uniqueness in scale values and thresholds is found in semiorders and interval orders.
- Published
- 2008
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
37. Continuous representability of interval orders: The topological compatibility setting
- Author
-
J. Gutiérrez García, Esteban Induráin, Asier Estevan, Gianni Bosi, Bosi, Gianni, Estevan, A., Garciá, J. Gutiérrez, and Induraín, E.
- Subjects
cInterval orders and semiorders ,Discrete mathematics ,continuous numerical representability ,Semiorder ,Topological space ,Topology ,Artificial Intelligence ,Control and Systems Engineering ,Compatibility (mechanics) ,Interval order ,cInterval orders and semiorders, continuous numerical representability ,Software ,Information Systems ,Mathematics - Abstract
In this paper, we go further on the problem of the continuous numerical representability of interval orders defined on topological spaces. A new condition of compatibility between the given topology and the indifference associated to the main trace of an interval order is introduced. Provided that this condition is fulfilled, a semiorder has a continuous interval order representation through a pair of continuous real-valued functions. Other necessary and sufficient conditions for the continuous representability of interval orders are also discussed, and, in particular, a characterization is achieved for the particular case of interval orders defined on a topological space of finite support.
- Published
- 2015
38. Bi-semiorders with frontiers on finite sets
- Author
-
Denis Bouyssou, Thierry Marchant, Laboratoire d'analyse et modélisation de systèmes pour l'aide à la décision (LAMSADE), Université Paris Dauphine-PSL, Université Paris sciences et lettres (PSL)-Université Paris sciences et lettres (PSL)-Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique (CNRS), Department of Data Analysis, and Universiteit Gent = Ghent University [Belgium] (UGENT)
- Subjects
Conjoint measurement ,Applied Mathematics ,Dimension (graph theory) ,Semiorder ,Interval order ,Extension (predicate logic) ,16. Peace & justice ,Bi-semiorder ,Frontier ,Combinatorics ,Product (mathematics) ,Biorder ,[INFO]Computer Science [cs] ,Finite set ,General Psychology ,Mathematics - Abstract
Document de travail: Cahier du LAMSADE, n°348 (2013); International audience; This paper studies an extension of bi-semiorders in which a “frontier” is added between the various relations used. This extension is motivated by the study of additive representations of ordered partitions and coverings defined on product sets of two components.
- Published
- 2015
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
39. Biased extensive measurement: The general case
- Author
-
Bertrand Lemaire and Marc Le Menestrel
- Subjects
Applied Mathematics ,Statistics ,Semiorder ,Measurement invariance ,Interval order ,Function (mathematics) ,Statistical physics ,Scale invariance ,General Psychology ,Independence (probability theory) ,Axiom ,Mathematics ,Homothetic transformation - Abstract
We develop a theory of biased extensive measurement which allows us to prove the existence of a ratio-scale without transitivity of indifference and with a property of homothetic invariance weaker than independence. These representations, which cover the cases of interval orders and of semiorders, reveal a unique biasing function smaller or equal to 1 that distorts extensive measurement and explains departures from its standard axioms. We interpret this biasing function as characterizing the qualitative influence of the underlying measurement process and we show that it induces a proportional indifference threshold.
- Published
- 2006
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
40. A representation for intransitive indifference relations
- Author
-
Emel Filiz and Erkut Y. Ozbay
- Subjects
Sociology and Political Science ,Just-noticeable difference ,Binary relation ,Semiorder ,General Social Sciences ,Interval (mathematics) ,Power (physics) ,Combinatorics ,Error function ,Interval order ,Statistics, Probability and Uncertainty ,Representation (mathematics) ,General Psychology ,Mathematics - Abstract
Binary relations representable by utility functions with multiplicative error are considered. It is proved that if the error is a power of utility then the underlying binary relation is either an interval order, or a semiorder. Moreover, semiorders can be characterized among interval orders by the magnitude of the power of utility that is used in the form of error function.
- Published
- 2005
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
41. The pseudo-transitivity of preference relations: Strict and weak (m,n)-Ferrers properties
- Author
-
Giarlotta, Alfio and Watson, S.
- Subjects
Transitivity ,Semitransitivity ,Strong semiorder ,Preference modeling ,Ferrers property ,Interval order ,Semiorder ,Strong interval order ,NaP-preference - Published
- 2014
42. Conditions for the Upper Semicontinuous Representability of Preferences with Nontransitive Indifference
- Author
-
Magalì E. Zuanon, Gianni Bosi, Bosi, Gianni, and Zuanon, M.
- Subjects
Pure mathematics ,Semiorder ,Upper Semicontinuous Numerical Representation ,Second-countable space ,Interval order ,Topological space ,Interval Order ,Mathematics - Abstract
We present different conditions for the existence of a pair of upper semicontinuous functions representing an interval order on a topological space without imposing any restrictive assumptions neither on the topological space nor on the representing functions. The particular case of second countable topological spaces, which is particularly interesting and frequent in economics, is carefully considered. Some final considerations concerning semiorders finish the paper.
- Published
- 2014
43. [Untitled]
- Author
-
Margarita Zudaire, Esteban Induráin, Gianni Bosi, Esteban Oloriz, and Juan Carlos Candeal
- Subjects
Discrete mathematics ,Transitive relation ,Algebra and Number Theory ,Computational Theory and Mathematics ,Relation (database) ,Semiorder ,Structure (category theory) ,Interval (graph theory) ,Interval order ,Geometry and Topology ,Algebra over a field ,Representation (mathematics) ,Mathematics - Abstract
In the framework of the analysis of orderings whose associated indifference relation is not necessarily transitive, we study the structure of an interval order and its representability through a pair of real-valued functions. We obtain a list of characterizations of the existence of a representation, showing that the three main techniques that have been used in the literature to achieve numerical representations of interval orders are indeed equivalent.
- Published
- 2001
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
44. [Untitled]
- Author
-
James A. Reeds and Peter C. Fishburn
- Subjects
Combinatorics ,Discrete mathematics ,Mathematics::Combinatorics ,Algebra and Number Theory ,Computational Theory and Mathematics ,Semiorder ,Interval (graph theory) ,Interval order ,Geometry and Topology ,Algebra over a field ,Partially ordered set ,Mathematics ,Unit interval - Abstract
A poset P=(X,≺) is a split semiorder if a unit interval and a distinguished point in that interval can be assigned to each x∈X so that x≺y precisely when x's distinguished point precedes y's interval, and y's distinguished point follows x's interval. For each |X|≤10, we count the split semiorders and identify all posets that are minimal forbidden posets for split semiorders.
- Published
- 2001
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
45. Necessary and possible preference structures
- Author
-
Salvatore Greco and Alfio Giarlotta
- Subjects
Discrete mathematics ,Economics and Econometrics ,Transitive relation ,Modal utility representation ,Binary relation ,Applied Mathematics ,Incomplete preference ,Preference resolution ,Semiorder ,Preorder ,Extension (predicate logic) ,NaP-preference ,Combinatorics ,Intransitive indifference ,Total preorder ,Completeness (order theory) ,Interval order ,Preference (economics) ,Mathematics - Abstract
A classical approach to model a preference on a set A of alternatives uses a reflexive, transitive and complete binary relation, i.e. a total preorder. Since the axioms of a total preorder do not usually hold in many applications, preferences are often modeled by means of weaker binary relations, dropping either completeness (e.g. partial preorders) or transitivity (e.g. interval orders and semiorders). We introduce an alternative approach to preference modeling, which uses two binary relations–the necessary preference ≿ N and the possible preference ≿ P –to fulfill completeness and transitivity in a mixed form. Formally, a NaP-preference (necessary and possible preference) on A is a pair ( ≿ N , ≿ P ) such that ≿ N is a partial preorder on A and ≿ P is an extension of ≿ N satisfying mixed properties of transitivity and completeness. We characterize a NaP-preference ( ≿ N , ≿ P ) by the existence of a nonempty set R of total preorders such that ⋂ R = ≿ N and ⋃ R = ≿ P . In order to analyze the representability of NaP-preferences via families of utility functions, we generalize the notion of a multi-utility representation of a partial preorder by that of a modal utility representation of a pair of binary relations. Further, we give a dynamic view of the family of all NaP-preferences on a fixed set A by endowing it with a relation of partial order, which is defined according to the stability of the information represented by each NaP-preference.
- Published
- 2013
46. A genesis of interval orders and semiorders: transitive NaP-preferences
- Author
-
Alfio Giarlotta
- Subjects
Discrete mathematics ,Transitive relation ,Algebra and Number Theory ,Strong semiorder ,Preorder ,Semiorder ,Mixed transitivity ,Interval order ,Interval (mathematics) ,NaP-preference ,Combinatorics ,Computational Theory and Mathematics ,Strong interval order ,Geometry and Topology ,Algebra over a field ,Mathematics - Abstract
A NaP-preference (necessary and possible preference) on a set A is a pair ${\left(\succsim^{^{_N}}\!,\,\succsim^{^{_P}}\!\right)}$ of binary relations on A such that its necessary component ${\succsim^{^{_N}} \!\!}$ is a partial preorder, its possible component ${\succsim^{^{_P}} \!\!}$ is a completion of ${\succsim^{^{_N}} \!\!}$ , and the two components jointly satisfy natural forms of mixed completeness and mixed transitivity. We study additional mixed transitivity properties of a NaP-preference ${\left(\succsim^{^{_N}}\!,\,\succsim^{^{_P}}\!\right)}$ , which culminate in the full transitivity of its possible component ${\succsim^{^{_P}} \!\!}$ . Interval orders and semiorders are strictly related to these properties, since they are the possible components of suitably transitive NaP-preferences. Further, we introduce strong versions of interval orders and semiorders, which are characterized by enhanced forms of mixed transitivity, and use a geometric approach to compare them to other well known preference relations.
- Published
- 2013
47. Tolerances, interval orders, and semiorders
- Author
-
Melvin F. Janowitz
- Subjects
Combinatorics ,Discrete mathematics ,General Mathematics ,Semiorder ,Interval (graph theory) ,Interval order ,Mathematics - Published
- 1994
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
48. Limits of interval orders and semiorders
- Author
-
Svante Janson
- Subjects
Discrete mathematics ,Semiorder ,Space (mathematics) ,Combinatorics ,06A06 ,FOS: Mathematics ,Interval (graph theory) ,Mathematics - Combinatorics ,Interval order ,Combinatorics (math.CO) ,Limit (mathematics) ,Special case ,Representation (mathematics) ,Partially ordered set ,Mathematics - Abstract
We study poset limits given by sequences of finite interval orders or, as a special case, finite semiorders. In the interval order case, we show that every such limit can be represented by a probability measure on the space of closed subintervals of [0,1], and we define a subset of such measures that yield a unique representation. In the semiorder case, we similarly find unique representations by a class of distribution functions., 18 pages
- Published
- 2011
49. Biorders with frontier
- Author
-
Thierry Marchant, Denis Bouyssou, Laboratoire d'analyse et modélisation de systèmes pour l'aide à la décision (LAMSADE), Université Paris Dauphine-PSL, Université Paris sciences et lettres (PSL)-Université Paris sciences et lettres (PSL)-Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique (CNRS), Department of Data Analysis, Universiteit Gent = Ghent University [Belgium] (UGENT), Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique (CNRS)-Université Paris Dauphine-PSL, and Université Paris sciences et lettres (PSL)-Université Paris sciences et lettres (PSL)
- Subjects
Relation (database) ,MODELS ,Semiorder ,CATEGORIES ,02 engineering and technology ,Interval (mathematics) ,PREFERENCES ,SEMIORDERS ,01 natural sciences ,Frontier ,Combinatorics ,0202 electrical engineering, electronic engineering, information engineering ,Interval order ,0101 mathematics ,Representation (mathematics) ,INTRANSITIVE INDIFFERENCE ,ComputingMilieux_MISCELLANEOUS ,Mathematics ,UTILITY ,Algebra and Number Theory ,INTERVAL ORDERS ,010102 general mathematics ,Extension (predicate logic) ,[SHS.ECO]Humanities and Social Sciences/Economics and Finance ,TIME ,Mathematics and Statistics ,Computational Theory and Mathematics ,Product (mathematics) ,Biorder ,020201 artificial intelligence & image processing ,Geometry and Topology ,NUMERICAL REPRESENTATION - Abstract
This paper studies an extension of biorders that has a “frontier” between the relation and the absence of relation. This extension is motivated by a conjoint measurement problem consisting in the additive representation of ordered coverings defined on product sets of two components. We also investigate interval orders and semiorders with frontier.
- Published
- 2011
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
50. A selection of maximal elements under non-transitive indifferences
- Author
-
Gianni Bosi, José Carlos R. Alcantud, Magalì Zuanon, Alcantud, J. C. R., Bosi, Gianni, and Zuanon, M.
- Subjects
Discrete mathematics ,Transitive relation ,Selection (relational algebra) ,Binary relation ,Applied Mathematics ,Selection of maximal ,Semiorder ,jel:D11 ,Interval order ,Acyclicity ,Set (abstract data type) ,Combinatorics ,Intransitivity ,Maximal element ,Selection of maximals ,General Psychology ,Mathematics - Abstract
In this work we are concerned with maximality issues under intransitivity of the indifference. Our approach relies on the analysis of "undominated maximals" (cf., Peris and Subiza, J Math Psychology 2002). Provided that an agent's binary relation is acyclic, this is a selection of its maximal elements that can always be done when the set of alternatives is finite. In the case of semiorders, proceeding in this way is the same as using Luce's selected maximals. We put forward a sufficient condition for the existence of undominated maximals for interval orders without any cardinality restriction. Its application to certain type of continuous semiorders is very intuitive and accommodates the well-known "sugar example" by Luce.
- Published
- 2009
Catalog
Discovery Service for Jio Institute Digital Library
For full access to our library's resources, please sign in.