189 results on '"Reasonable person"'
Search Results
2. From Clapham to Salina: Locating the Reasonable Man.
- Author
-
Stern, Simon
- Abstract
"The man on the Clapham omnibus" is an often cited but poorly understood name for the standard of reasonable care in tort. It originated in a 1903 decision in which this formula was used not to articulate a legal standard but to describe an average person whose views have no legal significance. This figure finds a cousin in another personification, as "the man who takes the magazines at home, and in the evening pushes the lawn-mower in his shirt sleeves." Both formulations have complex histories that help to underscore their inaptness as descriptors for the standard they are used to represent. These two examples also help to show, more generally, why a personified standard ("the reasonable person") tends to introduce problems that do not arise with a more abstract one ("reasonableness," "reasonable care"). Many critics have shown that the "reasonableness" standard is susceptible to problems of bias and framing. Personifying the standard invites the inappropriate use of individuated figures with particular features (e.g., a bus rider from a London suburb) that only worsen these problems. This article traces the history of these two standards, tries to explain how they moved from descriptive to normative use, and then turns to problems with personified standards more generally, showing how some superficially appealing reasons for using a personified standard prove to be unpersuasive. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2024
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
3. Provocation and the Reasonable Asian: Applying the Reasonable Person Standard to Asian Defendants Asserting the Provocation Defense
- Author
-
Kaitlyn Hyun
- Subjects
Reasonable person ,provocation ,criminal law ,cultural defense ,Asians ,Asian Americans ,immigrants ,murder ,manslaughter ,expert cultural witnesses ,defenses ,Law of Europe ,KJ-KKZ ,Law in general. Comparative and uniform law. Jurisprudence ,K1-7720 - Abstract
This Article examines the criminal law defense of provocation in the U.S., which employs an objective reasonable person standard, as applied to recent Asian immigrants. It discusses approaches taken in other countries and describes the cultural defense. The Article concludes with different possibilities for a hypothetical Asian defendant who was provoked: Improving education about U.S. laws as a preventative measure, using expert cultural witnesses at trial, and taking the defendant’s characteristics into consideration during the sentencing stage.
- Published
- 2024
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
4. Provocation and the Reasonable Asian: Applying the Reasonable Person Standard to Asian Defendants Asserting the Provocation Defense.
- Author
-
Hyun, Kaitlyn
- Subjects
ASIANS ,ASIAN Americans ,EXPERT evidence ,CRIMINAL defense ,CRIMINAL law - Abstract
This Article examines the criminal law defense of provocation in the U.S., which employs an objective reasonable person standard, as applied to recent Asian immigrants. It discusses approaches taken in other countries and describes the cultural defense. The Article concludes with different possibilities for a hypothetical Asian defendant who was provoked: Improving education about U.S. laws as a preventative measure, using expert cultural witnesses at trial, and taking the defendant's characteristics into consideration during the sentencing stage. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2024
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
5. Empathy at War: The Distinction Between Reasonableness and the Reasonable Military Commander Standard
- Author
-
Jeutner, Valentin, Hayashi, Nobuo, editor, and Lingaas, Carola, editor
- Published
- 2024
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
6. Self-Defense: Reasonable Beliefs or Reasonable Self-Control?
- Author
-
Simons, Kenneth W
- Subjects
Crime ,Criminal Law ,Self-Defense ,Justification ,Culpability ,Reasonable Person - Published
- 2022
7. Magical Thinking and Appearance-based Recusal.
- Author
-
Pines, Zygmont
- Subjects
COMMON law ,FAIRNESS ,JUDICIAL ethics ,JURISPRUDENCE ,CRITICAL analysis ,RULE of law - Abstract
This article is a critical analysis of a fundamental judicial ethic, the appearance of impartiality, an increasingly important public issue that is poorly understood and woefully underexamined in jurisprudence and academic literature. The ethic is pivotal to the determination of judicial disqualification, a/k/a recusal, and the public's fragile trust in the rule of law. The article explains how a mysterious metaphorical device, the "reasonable observer" (a descendant of the common law's "reasonable man") has been subjectively applied in a confusing and inconsistent manner in judicial disqualification cases. The unexamined approach has unwittingly undermined the plain text and the mandatory ethical obligation of recusal (i.e., a judge must disqualify when his or her impartiality might reasonably be questioned). The discussion: (a) analyzes the theoretical underpinnings of the reasonable person-observer analytical tool ("heuristic"); (b) explains how American jurisprudence has glibly transmogrified the appearance-recusal precept; (c) provides a unique and starkly contrasting analytical perspective demonstrating how select common law-based jurisdictions (Australia, Canada, Singapore, South Africa, United Kingdom) have painstakingly examined and applied the widely-recognized norm of appearance-based impartiality; and (d) synthesizes the preceding theoretical and jurisprudential information to support a proposal for a recalibrated metric and a pragmatic, clarifying heuristic. The article concludes with a model provision, in the form of a guiding "commentary," that summarizes the essential aspects of the appearance of bias precept. The article provides an interpretative approach that attempts to be faithful to the letter and spirit of the foundational judicial ethic. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2024
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
8. Self-Defense: Reasonable Beliefs or Reasonable Self-Control?
- Author
-
Simons, Kenneth W
- Subjects
Crime ,Criminal Law ,Self-Defense ,Justification ,Culpability ,Reasonable Person - Published
- 2021
9. Informed consent, price transparency, and disclosure.
- Author
-
Director, Samuel
- Subjects
- *
HOSPITAL charges , *MEDICAL quality control , *ACADEMIC dissertations , *INFORMED consent (Medical law) , *PATIENT decision making , *MEDICAL care costs , *DISCLOSURE , *ACCESS to information - Abstract
In the American medical system, patients do not know the final price of treatment until long after the treatment is given, at which point it is too late to say "no." I argue that without price disclosure many, perhaps all, tokens of consent in clinical medicine fall below the standard of valid, informed consent. This is a sweeping and broad thesis. The reason for this thesis is surprisingly simple: medical services rarely have prices attached to them that are known to the patient prior to treatment. Yet, for many patients, knowledge of the price is relevant to whether they would give consent. If informed consent requires that patients know all information about their treatment that is relevant to their decision, then consent to a medical intervention in the absence of the price is not informed consent. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2023
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
10. Deus ex machina : legal fictions in private law
- Author
-
Shmilovits, Liron and Ibbetson, David John
- Subjects
346 ,law ,private law ,legal fictions ,fiction ,legal history ,legal theory ,legal reasoning ,equity ,tort ,contract ,defamation ,estoppel ,remoteness ,reasonable man ,reasonable person ,trusts ,common intention constructive trust ,equitable maxim ,single meaning rule ,benefit of clergy ,bill of middlesex ,writ of quominus ,vi er armis ,ejectment ,quasi contract ,trover ,common recovery ,geographical fictions ,Volenti non fit injuria - Abstract
This PhD dissertation is about legal fictions in private law. A legal fiction, broadly, is a false assumption knowingly relied upon by the courts. The main aim of the dissertation is to formulate a test for which fictions should be accepted and which rejected. Subsidiary aims include a better understanding of the fiction as a device and of certain individual fictions, past and present. This research is undertaken, primarily, to establish a rigorous system for the treatment of fictions in English law - which is lacking. Secondarily, it is intended to settle some intractable disputes, which have plagued the scholarship. These theoretical debates have hindered progress on the practical matters which affect litigants in the real world. The dissertation is divided into four chapters. The first chapter is a historical study of common-law fictions. The conclusions drawn thereform are the foundation of the acceptance test for fictions. The second chapter deals with the theoretical problems surrounding the fiction. Chiefly, it seeks precisely to define 'legal fiction', a recurrent problem in the literature. A solution, in the form of a two-pronged definition, is proposed, adding an important element to the acceptance test. The third chapter analyses modern-day fictions and recommends retention or abolition for each fiction. In the fourth chapter, the findings hitherto are synthesised into a general acceptance test for fictions. This test, which is the thesis of this work, is presented as a flowchart. It is the author's hope that this project will raise awareness as to the merits and demerits of legal fictions, de-mystify the debate and bring about reform.
- Published
- 2019
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
11. Beyond Forensic Poetry: Lyric and Legal Languages in Contemporary Poems.
- Author
-
Gallerani, Guido Mattia
- Subjects
LEGAL language ,LEGAL literature ,POETRY (Literary form) ,LYRIC poetry ,LEGAL education - Abstract
In the field of Law and Literature studies, contributions on poetry are rare. This article focuses on a selection of contemporary poetic works: Cornelius Eady's A Brutal Imagination (2001), Frédéric Boyer's Le Goût du suicide lent (1999), Maurizio Cucchi's Il disperso (1976) and Corrado Benigni's Tribunale della mente (2012). Their lyrical shaping of law establishes a difference from the model of "forensic" poetry that can be found in Charles Reznikoff's Testimony (1978–1979). Through them, this contribution shows how it is possible to challenge a reflection on the language of lyric poetry and that of law at the same time, if we interpret the lyric poetry as a non-narrative discourse. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2022
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
12. When Risk Management Systems ‘Fail’: On Criminal Negligence and the Limits of Scientists’ Responsibility
- Author
-
Perin, Andrea, Gordijn, Bert, Series Editor, Roeser, Sabine, Series Editor, O'Mathúna, Dónal P., editor, and de Miguel Beriain, Iñigo, editor
- Published
- 2019
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
13. Insanity Assessment: Not Guilty by Reason of Insanity
- Author
-
Goldwaser, Alberto M., Goldwaser, Eric L., Goldwaser, Alberto M., and Goldwaser, Eric L.
- Published
- 2019
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
14. Knowledge and reasonableness.
- Author
-
Lawlor, Krista
- Subjects
STRUGGLE - Abstract
The notion of relevance plays a role in many accounts of knowledge and knowledge ascription. Although use of the notion is well-motivated, theorists struggle to codify relevance. A reasonable person standard of relevance addresses this codification problem, and provides an objective and flexible standard of relevance; however, treating relevance as reasonableness seems to allow practical factors to determine whether one has knowledge or not—so-called "pragmatic encroachment." I argue that a fuller understanding of reasonableness and of the role of practical factors in the acquisition of knowledge lets us avoid pragmatic encroachment. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2021
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
15. The Reasonable Person Standard: Psychological and Legal Perspectives.
- Author
-
Alicke, Mark D. and Weigel, Stephanie H.
- Subjects
SELF-defense ,NEGLIGENCE ,TORTS ,SELF - Abstract
In criminal cases of self-defense and provocation, and civil cases of negligence, culpability is often decided with reference to how a reasonably prudent person (RPP) would have behaved in similar circumstances. The RPP is said to be an objective standard in that it eschews consideration of a defendant's unique background or characteristics. We discuss theory and evidence suggesting that in morally relevant judgments, including those involving negligence, self-defense, and provocation, the tendency to rely on the self—on one's own values and predilections—dominates considerations of the RPP. We consider subjective standards that have been proposed as alternatives to the RPP and review research on this topic. We conclude by considering avenues for future research, particularly addressing conditions in which self-standards of reasonableness are most likely to prevail. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2021
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
16. Sexual Harassment
- Author
-
Browne, Kingsley R. and Buss, David M., book editor
- Published
- 2022
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
17. On the Reasonable Audience
- Author
-
Sedgman, Kirsty and Sedgman, Kirsty
- Published
- 2018
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
18. Family Torts and Remedies
- Author
-
Houlgate, Laurence D., Sellers, Mortimer, Series editor, Cudd, Ann E., Series editor, and Houlgate, Laurence D.
- Published
- 2017
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
19. The Standard of the Reasonable Person in Determining Negligence – Comparative Conclusions.
- Author
-
Ahmed, R.
- Subjects
- *
CHILDREN with disabilities , *NEGLIGENCE , *DISABILITIES - Abstract
The standard of the reasonable person or its equivalent, in general, is used in many jurisdictions to determine fault in the form of negligence. Although the standard is predominantly objective it is also subjective in that the subjective attributes of the person against whom the standard applies as well as the subjective circumstances present at the time of the delict or tort lend themselves to an objective-subjective application. In South African law, before a person can be judged according to the standard of the reasonable person, the person must first be held accountable. If a person cannot be held accountable, then the standard does not apply at all. The general standard of the reasonable person cannot be applied to children, the elderly, persons with physical disabilities, persons with mental impairments or experts. Therefore, depending on the subjective attributes of the person against whom the standard is being applied, the standard may have to be adjusted accordingly. The general standard of the reasonable person would be raised when dealing with experts, for instance, and lowered when dealing with persons with physical disabilities. This contribution considers whether the current application of the standard of the reasonable person in South African law is satisfactory when applied generally to all persons, no matter their age, experience, gender, physical disability and cognitive ability. The application of the standard of the reasonable person in South African law is compared to the application of the standard of the reasonable person or its equivalent in the United Kingdom, the United States of America and France. Just as South African law applies the standard of the reasonable expert to experts, this contribution explores whether the South African law should be developed to use similar adjusted standards when dealing with children, the elderly, persons with physical disabilities and so on. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2021
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
20. Is the Reasonable Person a Person of Virtue?
- Author
-
Mangini, Michele
- Subjects
REASONABLE person standard (Law) ,TORTS ,CRIMINAL law ,MARRIAGE law ,ETHICS - Abstract
The 'reasonable person standard' (RPS) is often called on in difficult legal cases as the last resource to be appealed to when other solutions run out. Its complexity derives from the controversial tasks that people place on it. Two dialectics require some clarification: the objective/subjective interpretation of the standard and the ideal/ordinary person controversy. I shall move through these dialectics from the standpoint of an EV (ethics of virtues) approach, assuming that on this interpretation the RPS can perform most persuasively its tasks. The all-round model of phronetic agent that I present not only works better than competing models—such as the utilitarian–economic and the Rawlsian—in the law of tort but shows its best potentialities in other kinds of cases. In criminal law and matrimonial law cases the recourse to the EV approach offers through the virtues rich and substantial resources to evaluate conflictual cases. This approach makes the threshold of evaluation much closer to real life than competitors. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2020
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
21. The Influence of Contemporary Combat on the Modern Soldier: A Force for Good or Bad
- Author
-
O’Sullivan, Carmel, Walters, Reece, Series editor, Drake, Deborah, Series editor, and O'Sullivan, Carmel
- Published
- 2016
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
22. A Pragmatic Framework of Values and Principles: The Beginning
- Author
-
Cooley, Dennis R., Weisstub, David N., Series editor, and Cooley, Dennis R.
- Published
- 2015
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
23. The Reasonable Victim of Modern Slavery.
- Author
-
Simpson, Bethany
- Subjects
- *
SLAVERY , *VICTIMS - Abstract
Reasonable person, relevant characteristics, realistic alternative, human trafficking, cannabis cultivation. [Extracted from the article]
- Published
- 2019
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
24. Between the Reasonable and the Particular: Deflating Autonomy in the Legal Regulation of Informed Consent to Medical Treatment.
- Author
-
Dunn, Michael, Fulford, K. W. M., Herring, Jonathan, and Handa, Ashok
- Subjects
INFORMED consent (Medical law) ,AUTONOMY (Psychology) ,CONFLICT (Psychology) ,DECISION making ,PATIENT autonomy - Abstract
The law of informed consent to medical treatment has recently been extensively overhauled in England. The 2015 Montgomery judgment has done away with the long-held position that the information to be disclosed by doctors when obtaining valid consent from patients should be determined on the basis of what a reasonable body of medical opinion agree ought to be disclosed in the circumstances. The UK Supreme Court concluded that the information that is material to a patient's decision should instead be judged by reference to a new two-limbed test founded on the notions of the 'reasonable person' and the 'particular patient'. The rationale outlined in Montgomery for this new test of materiality, and academic comment on the ruling's significance, has focused on the central ethical importance that the law now (rightfully) accords to respect for patient autonomy in the process of obtaining consent from patients. In this paper, we dispute the claim that the new test of materiality articulated in Montgomery equates with respect for autonomy being given primacy in re-shaping the development of the law in this area. We also defend this position, arguing that our revised interpretation of Montgomery's significance does not equate with a failure by the courts to give due legal consideration to what is owed to patients as autonomous decision-makers in the consent process. Instead, Montgomery correctly implies that doctors are ethically (and legally) obliged to attend to a number of relevant ethical considerations in framing decisions about consent to treatment, which include subtle interpretations of the values of autonomy and well-being. Doctors should give appropriate consideration to how these values are fleshed out and balanced in context in order to specify precisely what information ought to be disclosed to a patient as a requirement of obtaining consent, and as a core component of shared decision-making within medical encounters more generally. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2019
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
25. The common rule's 'reasonable person' standard for informed consent.
- Author
-
Greenblum, Jake and Hubbard, Ryan
- Subjects
- *
INFORMED consent (Medical law) , *REASONABLE person standard (Law) , *INSTITUTIONAL review boards , *HUMAN research subjects - Abstract
Laura Odwazny and Benjamin Berkman have raised several challenges regarding the new reasonable person standard in the revised Common Rule, which states that informed consent requires potential research subjects be provided with information a reasonable person would want to know to make an informed decision on whether to participate in a study. Our aim is to offer a response to the challenges Odwazny and Berkman raise, which include the need for a reasonable person standard that can be applied consistently across institutional review boards and that does not stigmatize marginal groups. In response, we argue that the standard ought to be based in an ordinary rather than ideal person conception of reasonable person and that the standard ought to employ what we call a liberal constraint: the reasonability standard must be malleable enough such that a wide variety of individuals with different, unique value systems would endorse it. We conclude by suggesting some of the likely consequences our view would have, if adopted. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2019
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
26. Concluding Thoughts : President and CEO, Moving beyond Prejudice
- Author
-
Saltzman, Paul, Boske, Christa, editor, and Osanloo, Azadeh, editor
- Published
- 2015
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
27. The reasonable person - relevance, normality, controllability
- Author
-
Siying Zhang, Wu, Sarah A, and Gerstenberg, Tobias
- Subjects
FOS: Psychology ,psychology and law ,Cognitive Psychology ,Psychology ,Social and Behavioral Sciences ,reasonable person - Abstract
Investigating how people understand the reasonable person
- Published
- 2023
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
28. The reasonable person - outcomes
- Author
-
Gerstenberg, Tobias, Siying Zhang, and Wu, Sarah A
- Subjects
FOS: Psychology ,psychology and law ,Cognitive Psychology ,Psychology ,Social and Behavioral Sciences ,reasonable person - Abstract
Investigating how people understand the reasonable person
- Published
- 2023
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
29. Freedom of Speech, Cyberspace, Harassment Law, and the Clinton Administration
- Author
-
Eugene Volokh
- Subjects
Plaintiff ,Legal liability ,Law ,media_common.quotation_subject ,Harassment ,Offensive ,Doctrine ,Sociology ,Cyberspace ,Reasonable person ,Supreme court ,media_common - Abstract
During the height of the Clinton-Lewinsky scandal, some lawyer pundits made some rather remarkable observations: Saying certain things about the scandal, they advised people, might be legally punishable. "Be careful what you say," one headline warned, when you discuss "the Starr report and Clinton/Lewinsky matter" in certain ways. Such discussions "ought to be avoided" because of the risk of legal liability. "[I]t's best to choose carefully who you share your remarks, your jokes, with....'Attorneys warn us about [legal liability],' she said. Office humor in particular 'is always quicksand'...." "There's no right [to make certain statements about the Clinton/Lewinsky affair] just because it's a public issue." "We had quite a few clients calling us when Lewinsky jokes...were making the rounds." "People think that if they hear something on TV or the radio they can say it at work [without fear of legal liability]. But that of course is not the case." What body of law, one might ask, would suppress jokes about the President, or discussion of the Starr Report? Not the most publicized free speech restriction of the Clinton years, the Communications Decency Act, which had been struck down 9-0 by the Supreme Court. Rather, this remarkable speech restriction is hostile environment harassment law. Under this doctrine, speech can lead to massive liability so long as it is "severe or pervasive" enough to create a "hostile, abusive, or offensive work environment" for the plaintiff and for a reasonable person based on the person's race, religion, sex, national origin, disability, age, veteran status, and so on. And these rather vague and broad terms have long been interpreted to cover not just face-to-face slurs or repeated indecent propositions, but also sexually themed jokes and discussions, even ones that aren't about coworkers or directed to particular coworkers. The prudent employer is wise to restrict speech like this, whether it's about Clinton, Lewinsky, Starr, or anyone else--not just because of professionalism concerns (which some employers might care more about and others less), but because of the risk that this speech will be found to have been illegal. This article explores, through the lens of four specific Clinton-era cyberspace "harassing speech" controversies, how hostile environment harassment law has rapidly become one of the broadest modern restrictions on speech generally, and on cyberspace speech in particular.
- Published
- 2022
30. Should the Model Penal Code's Mens Rea Provisions Be Amended?
- Author
-
Kenneth W. Simons
- Subjects
media_common.quotation_subject ,Ignorance ,Mistake ,Mens rea ,Reasonable person ,reckless ,mens rea ,Law ,Model Penal Code ,Criminal law ,recklessness ,mental state ,Sociology ,Element (criminal law) ,Recklessness ,criminal law ,media_common ,Law and economics - Abstract
The Model Penal Code approach to mens rea was a tremendous advance. The MPC carefully defines a limited number of mens rea terms, firmly establishes element analysis in place of offense analysis, and recognizes that the doctrine of mistake is part and parcel of the basic analysis of mens rea. However, a revised Code could improve the drafting of the mens rea provisions in a number of respects: * Clarify how to distinguish result, circumstance, and result elements * Simplify the definitions of knowledge and purpose * Perhaps eliminate the category of mens rea as to conduct * Clarify the fact/law distinction, and especially the distinction between two types of mistakes of law - mistakes of governing law and mistakes of legal element - that the MPC treats differently * Clarify the meaning of the "reasonable person" test * Clarify the definition of willful blindness Moreover, more fundamental questions arise with the central concept of recklessness. A reckless actor is one who must be aware of a "substantial and unjustifiable" risk; are these independent or interdependent requirements? What type or degree of consciousness is required? Of what, precisely, must the actor be aware? Does a strict "consciousness" requirement undermine the rule that ignorance of law is no excuse? And should consciousness extend to "latent" knowledge that the actor could call up if he were to consider the matter even for a moment? Furthermore, does the MPC hierarchy always work? Is knowledge really always worse than recklessness? Is recklessness always worse than negligence? Should culpable indifference or a similar mental state be added to the hierarchy? Are the MPC categories too cognitive, or too descriptive, or too rigid? Finally, the conclusion examines some theoretical and pragmatic implications of the analysis.
- Published
- 2022
31. ІНВЕРСІЇ «РОЗУМНОГО МИСЛЕННЯ» В КОНТЕКСТІ «КРИТИЧНОГО РАЦІОНАЛІЗМУ»
- Author
-
Гальченко, М. С.
- Abstract
The article deals with the problem of reasoning in the context of scientific rationality. As a variety of critical rationality, which includes the analysis a theory, that allows critical reflection and substantiation of facts. The author notes the need to distinguish between the concept of «rationality» and «reasonableness». Reasonableness becomes the foundation for the formation of reasoning. The formation of reasonable personalities is the main task of a rationally organized society. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2018
32. Situationism, capacities and culpability
- Author
-
Adam Piovarchy
- Subjects
Philosophy of language ,Philosophy of mind ,Philosophy ,Counterfactual conditional ,Situationism ,Wrongdoing ,media_common.quotation_subject ,Metaphysics ,Psychology ,Social psychology ,Reasonable person ,media_common ,Culpability - Abstract
The situationist experiments demonstrate that most people’s behaviour is influenced by environmental factors much more than we expect, and that ordinary people can be led to behave very immorally. A number of philosophers have investigated whether these experiments demonstrate that subjects’ responsibility-relevant capacities are impeded. This paper considers how, in practice, we can assess when agents have a reduced capacity to avoid wrongdoing. It critiques some previously offered strategies including appeals to the reasonable person standard, appeals to counterfactuals and understandability of behaviour, and appeals to base rates of wrongdoing. It then proposes we should think a certain factor impeded capacities when this is the best explanation of a change in patterns of responses. With this approach in hand, I then argue that subjects in many of the situationist experiments are (mostly) excused for their actions.
- Published
- 2021
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
33. The Reasonable Person Standard: Psychological and Legal Perspectives
- Author
-
Stephanie H. Weigel and Mark D. Alicke
- Subjects
Blame ,Sociology and Political Science ,media_common.quotation_subject ,Law ,Provocation test ,Criminal law ,Tort ,Psychology ,Reasonable person ,media_common ,Culpability - Abstract
In criminal cases of self-defense and provocation, and civil cases of negligence, culpability is often decided with reference to how a reasonably prudent person (RPP) would have behaved in similar circumstances. The RPP is said to be an objective standard in that it eschews consideration of a defendant's unique background or characteristics. We discuss theory and evidence suggesting that in morally relevant judgments, including those involving negligence, self-defense, and provocation, the tendency to rely on the self—on one's own values and predilections—dominates considerations of the RPP. We consider subjective standards that have been proposed as alternatives to the RPP and review research on this topic. We conclude by considering avenues for future research, particularly addressing conditions in which self-standards of reasonableness are most likely to prevail.
- Published
- 2021
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
34. Perceptions of custody: Similarities and disparities among police, judges, social psychologists, and laypeople
- Author
-
Saul M. Kassin and Fabiana Alceste
- Subjects
Adult ,Freedom ,Male ,media_common.quotation_subject ,Video Recording ,Reasonable person ,Judgment ,Law Enforcement ,Arts and Humanities (miscellaneous) ,Perception ,Humans ,Psychology ,General Psychology ,media_common ,Social perception ,Middle Aged ,Psychiatry and Mental health ,Vignette ,Feeling ,Criminal law ,Female ,Suspect ,Law ,Social psychology ,Custodial interrogation - Abstract
OBJECTIVE Custody is a legal state that requires police to Mirandize suspects and, in some jurisdictions, to record their interrogation. The present study compared the custody perceptions of police, judges, social psychologists, and laypeople. HYPOTHESES We predicted that (a) high-custody vignettes would elicit less perceived freedom than low-custody vignettes; (b) police and judges would see these situations as less custodial relative to social psychologists and laypeople; (c) these differences would arise mostly in ambiguous vignettes; and (d) participants in general would perceive suspects as objectively having more freedom to leave than they subjectively feel they have. METHOD Police officers (n = 223), trial judges (n = 219), social psychologists (n = 228), and laypeople (n = 205) read a vignette of a police-suspect encounter that presented high-, ambiguous, or low-levels of custody and indicated their perceptions of the suspect's freedom to leave. RESULTS Participants perceived the most freedom in the low-custody vignettes, followed by ambiguous and high-custody vignettes, and all groups differed significantly from each other (ηp2 = .39). Police and judges overestimated how free they thought the suspect would feel compared to social psychologists and laypeople, who did not differ from each other (ηp2 = .085). Participants in general saw the suspect as objectively freer than they thought he felt, and themselves as feeling freer than they believed the suspect did (ηp2 = .35). Police defined a "reasonable person" as someone who is mentally stable, whereas judges were more likely to cite a person of average intelligence. CONCLUSION Despite the assumption that custody can be defined by the effects of objective circumstances on the reasonable person, results revealed substantial variation of perceptions between police and judges on the one hand, and social psychologists and laypeople on the other. As a result, legal safeguards triggered by custodial interrogation may be inconsistently applied to real suspects. (PsycInfo Database Record (c) 2021 APA, all rights reserved).
- Published
- 2021
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
35. Competition Overdose: How Free Market Mythology Transformed Us from Citizen Kings to Market Servants by Maurice E Stucke and Ariel Ezrachi. USA: Harper Business, 2020, 402 pp ($32.50 paperback). ISBN: 978-0-06-289283-6
- Author
-
Oles Andriychuk
- Subjects
Writing style ,Competition (economics) ,Politics ,Political science ,media_common.quotation_subject ,Normative ,Ideology ,Free market ,Competition law ,Law ,Reasonable person ,Law and economics ,media_common - Abstract
The new book by two prominent competition law thinkers Maurice E. Stucke (Professor of Law at the University of Tennessee) and Ariel Ezrachi (Professor of Law at the University of Oxford) 'Competition Overdose: How Free Market Mythology Transformed Us from Citizen Kings to Market Servants' (Harper Business, USA, 2020, pp. 402) has triggered a vivid discussion over the ever-fading question on the goals of competition law, economics and policy and – more broadly – on the very nature of the multifaceted phenomenon of competition. The previous blockbuster of the tandem 'Virtual Competition: The Promise and Perils of the Algorithm-Driven Economy' (2016) has generated vocal and diverse feedback, and the authors continue their market success with publishing another thought-provoking piece. The book provokes not only thoughts. From its very title, subtitle, name of chapters, normative position, methodological argumentation and the choice of preprint reviewers, across the selection of case studies and to its very writing style, the book is designed to generate discussion. And for the right reasons. The times when competition policy was perceived as an axiomatic, mathematised, highly technical and pretty much non-controversial area of Law & Economics have gone. Over the last decade, competition has become a great theme again. Full of ideological appeals and statements, mindful of their political pedigree, competition law, economics and policy are transitioning from the mechanistic field of microeconomic modelling to the real world of geopolitical chessboards.A quick look at the composition of the book, makes clear the authors' intention to transpose their well-established and highly influential academic reasoning from the narrow world of competition theorists to the broader and more diverse audience. The key objective of the book in this respect is to convince such broader societal circles of the need to reform competition policy – or rather to revise our perception of the very essence and the very mission of economic competition as such. The book is in several senses iconoclastic. As skilful diagnosticians, the authors reveal weakness after weakness of the market-centred ethics. The main cures offered by the book – both in terms of the normative propositions as well as the politicised vocabulary and intentionally approachable argumentative apparatus – will be appealing to many. The authors aim to raise (or perhaps to refine) the ethical dimension in the otherwise morally neutral phenomenon of economic competition and its regulation, and this book's objective and mission are remarkable in themselves. It is hard to find a reasonable person disagreeing with the normative premises of the book. It is much easier to find one disagreeing with the enforceability of these intentions. In what follows I’ll try to articulate ten polemical points, written as a reflection on the book. Only a few of these points express disagreement. All are written with deep and sincere respect to both authors – the Masters of the discipline. We agree on most of the things, disagreeing rather on nuances. I believe though that some of those nuances are important.
- Published
- 2021
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
36. Conservative liberalism: Hume, Smith, and Burke as policy liberals and polity conservatives
- Author
-
Daniel B. Klein
- Subjects
Organizational Behavior and Human Resource Management ,Economics and Econometrics ,Presumption ,Jurisprudence ,05 social sciences ,06 humanities and the arts ,Conservatism ,Reasonable person ,0506 political science ,060104 history ,Politics ,Liberalism ,Political science ,050602 political science & public administration ,Political culture ,0601 history and archaeology ,Polity ,Law and economics - Abstract
On regular issues of policy reform—presupposing a stable integrated polity— Hume, Smith, and Burke were liberal in the original political meaning of “liberal.” Thus, on policy reform, although they accorded the status quo a certain presumption (as any reasonable person must), the more distinctive feature is that they maintained (even propounded, most plainly in Smith's case) a presumption of liberty in matters of policy reform. But we need another conceptualization that treats their attitudes about establishing, reforming, and securing the wider structure of political institutions, political procedure, and political culture and character—matters of polity reformation. On polity reformation, they showed sensibilities for which “conservative” is apt (though such conservatism was not otherwise purely neutral). Hume, Smith, and Burke were basically in agreement in the matters treated here. They are polity conservatives. The article develops the two conceptualizations—policy reform and polity reformation—, an understanding of “liberal” applicable to policy reform, and an understanding of “conservative” (namely, a heavy presumption of the status quo) that may be applied to policy reform and to polity reformation. If we code the three thinkers as PLPC (policy liberals and polity conservatives), we may put the matter this way: It would be meaningful but wrong to code them instead PCPC (policy conservatives and polity conservatives). I call their outlook conservative liberalism. I deal disproportionately with Burke, to tussle with two sets of imagined interlocutors, one on Burke as liberal, and the other on Burkean insight on polity reformation.
- Published
- 2021
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
37. Punishment and Precious Emotions: A Hope Standard for Punishment
- Author
-
Kimberley Brownlee
- Subjects
punishment ,Scope (project management) ,Punishment ,media_common.quotation_subject ,hope ,Prison ,Context (language use) ,Articles ,Criminology ,emotions ,life imprisonment ,Mental health ,self-harm ,Reasonable person ,prison ,AcademicSubjects/LAW00010 ,Psychology ,Law ,suicide ,Life imprisonment ,media_common - Abstract
— Each year, hundreds of people in high-income countries take their own lives while they are in prison. Thousands engage in self-harm and thousands abuse other prisoners. Such behaviours often correlate with mental health problems, but they are also often pleas for help and for hope. Some courts have invoked the ideas of hope and the right to hope in the context of life imprisonment, but they have neither subjected the concept of hope to sustained analysis nor specified the role that hope should play in our practices of lawful punishment overall. This article offers a preliminary investigation of the role for hope in lawful punishment. It argues that one standard that both individual modes of punishment and overall systems of punishment must meet to be morally justifiable is that they be compatible with a reasonable person retaining hope both in the present and for his future after punishment. Such a hope standard narrows the scope of legitimate modes of punishment.
- Published
- 2021
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
38. In defence of our model for just healthcare systems: why an explicit philosophy is needed in addition to the law, and how Scanlon helps derive just policies
- Author
-
Caitríona L Cox and Zoe Fritz
- Subjects
Value (ethics) ,Health (social science) ,Judicial review ,Computer science ,Health Policy ,06 humanities and the arts ,0603 philosophy, ethics and religion ,Reasonable person ,Philosophy ,03 medical and health sciences ,Issues, ethics and legal aspects ,Health services ,0302 clinical medicine ,Arts and Humanities (miscellaneous) ,Healthcare policy ,Work (electrical) ,Law ,Capability approach ,Humans ,060301 applied ethics ,030212 general & internal medicine ,Policy Making ,Delivery of Health Care ,Healthcare system - Abstract
In a recent response to our paper on developing a philosophical framework to guide the design and delivery of a just health service, Sarela raises several objections. We feel that although Sarela makes points which are worthy of discussion, his critique does not undermine either the need for, or the worth of, our proposed model. First, the law does not negate the need for ethics in determining just healthcare policy. Reliance on legal processes can drive inappropriate focus on ensuring policies avoid judicial review, as opposed to ensuring they are truly just; the law affords protection against unjust policies but does not put a commitment to avoiding them at the heart of policy-making. We defend the need for Scanlonian supplementation by emphasising the practical value of adding a step based on reasonable rejection, particularly in ensuring that the views of vulnerable stakeholders are robustly considered. We discuss the similarities and differences between the work of Daniels and Sen in considering the relationship between health and opportunity, concluding that Sen’s capability approach is both valuable and compatible with our proposed model. Finally, the practical use of our model requires consideration of what constitutes a reasonable person. Our model is explicitly intended to help develop a healthcare system which is just to all its users. With this in mind, we suggest that those involved in decision-making should meet Scanlon’s definition of reasonable: they should be motivated to justify their actions to, and seek agreement with, others.
- Published
- 2021
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
39. Must Consent Be Informed? Patient rights, state authority, and the moral basis of the physician’s duties of disclosure
- Author
-
D. Robert MacDougall
- Subjects
Freedom ,Moral Obligations ,Risk ,media_common.quotation_subject ,Disclosure ,Reasonable person ,State (polity) ,Argument ,Physicians ,Humans ,Ethics, Medical ,Political philosophy ,Duty ,media_common ,Physician-Patient Relations ,Informed Consent ,Interpretation (philosophy) ,Politics ,General Medicine ,Variety (cybernetics) ,Philosophy ,Patient Rights ,Government ,Law ,Psychology ,Autonomy - Abstract
Legal standards of disclosure in a variety of jurisdictions require physicians to inform patients about the likely consequences of treatment, as a condition for obtaining the patient's consent. Such a duty to inform is special insofar as extensive disclosure of risks and potential benefits is not usually a condition for obtaining consent in non-medical transactions.What could morally justify the physician's special legal duty to inform? I argue that existing justifications have tried but failed to ground such special duties directly in basic and general rights, such as autonomy rights. As an alternative to such direct justifications, I develop an indirect justification of physicians' special duties from an argument in Kant's political philosophy. Kant argues that pre-legal rights to freedom are the source of a duty to form a state. The state has the authority to conclusively determine what counts as "consent" in various kinds of transactions. The Kantian account can subsequently indirectly justify at least one legal standard imposing a duty to inform, the reasonable person standard, but rules out one interpretation of a competitor, the subjective standard.
- Published
- 2021
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
40. Duty of care in clinical education - Part 1
- Author
-
Keri Moore
- Subjects
030222 orthopedics ,Legal liability ,business.industry ,Compromise ,media_common.quotation_subject ,education ,Legislation ,Reasonable person ,03 medical and health sciences ,Patient safety ,0302 clinical medicine ,Complementary and alternative medicine ,Argument ,Duty of care ,Medicine ,Engineering ethics ,030212 general & internal medicine ,business ,Duty ,media_common - Abstract
Discourse regarding the legal position of osteopathic clinical educators is scarce. The educator-patient-student relationship is complex and if not managed well may compromise patient and student safety. This doctrinal research paper explores how Australian Civil Liability Legislation may be applied during clinical education. The paper constitutes a thought experiment and uses reasoning by analogy, applied to a hypothetical problem scenario, set during an osteopathic student's clinical practice event for the purpose of exploring the educator's duty relationships and to tease-out possible acts or omissions that could potentially be used in an argument designed to establish a clinical educators breach of duty. The deliberations presented here illuminate the complex relationships and highlight situations in which a reasonable person may consider the clinical educator has provided poor supervision of the student's work with patients. This concept paper signposts the potential vulnerability of the patient and the student if supervision standards are not maintained and if appropriate clinical standards are not applied. Possible lines of arguments a patient may raise or a student may raise in a negligence case as well as possible defences the clinical educator may offer are presented.
- Published
- 2020
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
41. Image of Good Faith Subjects of Law in Legal Cultural History: Definition of Universal Standards
- Author
-
Iryna Sharkova
- Subjects
Faith ,Public law ,Law ,media_common.quotation_subject ,Private law ,Sociology ,Praise ,United Nations Convention on Contracts for the International Sale of Goods ,Legal culture ,Reasonable person ,Principles of European Contract Law ,media_common - Abstract
The article is devoted to the problem of Good Faith Subjects` status in law. For a better understanding of the problem, image ofgood faith subjects of law in Ancient Rome was analyzed. In particular, it was found that in roman law, the term bonus pater familias(good family father) refers to a standard of good faith subjects of law. In the English version, this concept was translated as «that of aman of ordinary prudence in managing his own affairs».The concept of a gentleman in the English legal tradition is specially studied.English noun ‘gentleman’ dates back to the Old French word ‘gentilz hom’ (graceful, refined man). That was why the social ca -te gory of gentleman is considered as “the nearest, contemporary English equivalent of the noblesse of France.” (Maurice Hugh Keen).Now, a gentleman is not just any man of good and courteous conduct, but a certain person having legal personality in accordancewith the standard of common law.In conformity with the dimension of public law, the English social category of gentleman captures a right of certen classe of theBritish nobility.But in accordance with modern private law the connotation of the term gentleman corresponds to the Rome legal institute ofbonus pater familias.The double origin of this term from the status of a knight and the social position of the merchant causes a controversial interpretationsof its meaning.In contemporary usage, the word gentleman is ambiguously defined, because “to behave like a gentleman” communicates as littlepraise or as much criticism as the speaker means to imply; thus, “to spend money like a gentleman” is criticism, but “to conduct a businesslike a gentleman” is praise (Walter Alison Phillips).In modern International Trade Law a gentleman is essentially a ‘man of sense’, ‘а man of judgment’ or a reasonable person.So United Nations Convention on Contracts for the International Sale of Goods (1980), The UNIDROIT Principles of InternationalCommercial Contract and the Principles of European Contract Law provided a rule, which offers an opportunity for such an interpretation.‘the contract is to be interpreted according to the meaning that reasonable persons of the same kind as the parties would giveto it in the same circumstances’.It led to the conclusion that the modern image of a good faith subject to the greatest extent actualizes the criterion of commonsense.
- Published
- 2020
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
42. Duress and loss of control: fear and anger in excusatory defences
- Author
-
Glenys Williams
- Subjects
Mental state ,media_common.quotation_subject ,Anger ,Element (criminal law) ,Anger in ,Control (linguistics) ,Psychology ,Social psychology ,Preference ,Reasonable person ,media_common - Abstract
This article examines the role of the anger and fear emotions in the loss of control and duress defences and argues that, although fear is now included as a trigger in loss of control, priority is still given to anger as a triggering event. Furthermore, in duress, although fear is the overriding mental state of the duressee, it wrongly forms no part of the rationale of the defence at all. Following a brief examination of both emotions, the article – individually with respect to each defence – considers issues relating to the (in)sufficiency of the objective element contained in the defences, specifically because neither properly take fear into account as a characteristic which should be attributed to the reasonable person, and then, to a lesser extent, what impact theoretical principles, such as mechanistic and evaluative approaches, have on the role emotion plays in both defences (if any). It is clear that none of these, nor indeed the relatively new discipline of neuroscience, examined in the penultimate section of the article, can tell us about the effects of emotion on decision-making, reasoning, control and responsibility, nor can they provide an answer as to how emotions – fear especially – can be properly incorporated into both defences. Numerous emotion-based alternative solutions are disseminated, and, although no preference is expressed here, it is recommended, firstly, that fear should be more effectively incorporated into the loss of control defence and, secondly, that duress should include fear as a characteristic attributed to the reasonable person.
- Published
- 2020
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
43. Knowledge and reasonableness
- Author
-
Krista Lawlor
- Subjects
Philosophy of science ,05 social sciences ,General Social Sciences ,Metaphysics ,06 humanities and the arts ,0603 philosophy, ethics and religion ,050105 experimental psychology ,Reasonable person ,Epistemology ,Philosophy of language ,Philosophy ,Ascription ,060302 philosophy ,0501 psychology and cognitive sciences ,Relevance (information retrieval) ,Psychology - Abstract
The notion of relevance plays a role in many accounts of knowledge and knowledge ascription. Although use of the notion is well-motivated, theorists struggle to codify relevance. A reasonable person standard of relevance addresses this codification problem, and provides an objective and flexible standard of relevance; however, treating relevance as reasonableness seems to allow practical factors to determine whether one has knowledge or not—so-called “pragmatic encroachment.” I argue that a fuller understanding of reasonableness and of the role of practical factors in the acquisition of knowledge lets us avoid pragmatic encroachment.
- Published
- 2020
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
44. Is a Reasonable Woman Different from a Reasonable Person? Gender Differences in Perceived Sexual Harassment
- Author
-
Hank Rothgerber, Allison Farmer, Katie Kaufling, C. Blake Andrew, and Ciara G. Incorvati
- Subjects
Gender Studies ,Social Psychology ,Perception ,media_common.quotation_subject ,Developmental and Educational Psychology ,Harassment ,Young adult ,Psychology ,Social psychology ,Reasonable person ,Dyad ,media_common - Abstract
Although the problem of sexual harassment can be approached from a variety of perspectives, the present research focused on the role played by individuals’ perceptions, specifically those that may differ between men and women. We examined whether perceived sexual harassment would vary depending on observers’ gender, on gender of the harasser and of the victim, and on whether and what type of sexual harassment definition was provided to observers. In doing so, we attempted to update and clarify inconsistent results from prior studies. Results from 413 young adult U.S. MTurk participants responding to an online survey revealed fairly large effects for participants’ gender, such that women perceived a wider range of situations as sexual harassment than did men. In addition, the dyad of a man harassing a woman was construed as more definitely involving sexual harassment than other dyads. Surprisingly, these gender differences were smaller for situations judged as comprising sexual harassment to a lesser extent (i.e., those involving derogatory attitudes and nonsexual physical contact). Results are discussed in relation to prior findings and their legal implications, especially as they relate to a psychological assumption of the so-called “reasonable woman” standard used in U.S. courts, that women perceive sexual harassment to a greater degree than men. The results are also relevant for those wishing to curtail harassment within organizations and for those counseling victims of sexual harassment.
- Published
- 2020
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
45. Cyberbullying in Nigeria: Examining the Adequacy of Legal Responses
- Author
-
Adejoke O. Adediran
- Subjects
050101 languages & linguistics ,business.industry ,media_common.quotation_subject ,05 social sciences ,Internet privacy ,Shame ,Ignorance ,Criminal code ,Language and Linguistics ,Reasonable person ,Harm ,050501 criminology ,0501 psychology and cognitive sciences ,Social media ,Philosophy of law ,business ,Psychology ,Law ,Stalking ,0505 law ,media_common - Abstract
Cyberbullying has been defined as the “process of using the internet, cell phones or other devices to send or post text or images intended to hurt or embarrass another person.” The word “cyberbullying” is often used interchangeably with “cyber stalking” and in fact the Cybercrimes (Prohibition, Prevention, etc.) Act 2015 of Nigeria, uses the word “cyber stalking” which it defines as any course of conduct directed at a specific person that would cause a reasonable person to feel fear. By the provisions of the Act, the transmission of any communication through the means of a computer to bully, threaten or harass another person where such communication places another person in fear of death, violence or bodily harm amounts to cyber stalking. Cyberbullying is becoming a common phenomenon in Nigeria as more people engage in it especially on social media platforms. This is carried out in various ways and a common trend is posting indecent imagery of persons online such as naked pictures or videos of persons in order to humiliate them. When posted by a person, the communication is shared by others thereby causing circulation on social media. This act amounts to cyber stalking where the intention consists of those elements stated under the Cybercrimes Act. In other situations where it is shared without the aim of humiliating the victim, such act can still be incriminated under some other laws in Nigeria such as the Criminal Code Act and the Penal Code Act which for instance both criminalise obscene publications. It is worthy of note there have been reported cases where victims of cyberbullying have committed suicide as a result of fear or shame. A major observation is that cyberbullying has gained normalcy and many internet users engaged in it do not seem to be aware of the criminal connotation of their actions. This paper examines the effectiveness of legal responses to cyberbullying in Nigeria. It discusses the forms of cyberbullying commonly perpetrated in Nigeria by citing some real life instances that have happened in the past. The paper notes that most forms of cyberbullying can be prosecuted under the Cybercrimes Act, however, there has not been any notable enforcement of the law in terms of prosecution of cyberbullying cases. It appears that the lack of prosecution of offenders has fostered the act of cyberbullying especially under the present circumstances where there is widespread ignorance among internet users. The paper also notes that the absence of image rights is a precursor in many respects to some forms of cyberbullying especially when photographs and videos of victims are involved. The paper advocates the implementation and enforcement of the Cybercrimes Act as well as other laws relating to cyberbullying in Nigeria. The paper also posits that the protection of image rights will go a long way to assist in curbing the act of cyberbullying in Nigeria.
- Published
- 2020
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
46. Modern Urban Culture: a City for or against a Person?
- Author
-
O. V. Kireeva and M. N. Veselova
- Subjects
cities of russia ,media_common.quotation_subject ,B1-5802 ,city image ,Reasonable person ,HM401-1281 ,metropolis ,050906 social work ,Urban culture ,Sociology (General) ,0501 psychology and cognitive sciences ,Sociology ,Philosophy of culture ,Philosophy (General) ,Superficiality ,media_common ,Civilization ,Conceptualization ,05 social sciences ,Cultural heritage ,philosophy of culture ,city ,Aesthetics ,Philosophical analysis ,modern urban culture ,city concept ,0509 other social sciences ,urban area ,050104 developmental & child psychology - Abstract
Introduction. The paper attempts to find answers to the questions: will it be possible to preserve historical-cultural “face” of the city, or it will disappear under the onslaught of the advanced achievements of civilization; is there an urban space to a reasonable person, who have reached great technological heights, or directed against him; what are the ontological foundations of the modern city? The relevance of the author's approach is the analysis of the “concept” of the city as urogenous spatio-temporal macro model, which not only develops under the influence of the inhabitants, but also determines their worldview and behavior.Methodology and sources. Methodological basis of the work is the cultural and philosophical analysis of the “concept“ of the modern city in the works of domestic and foreign sociologists, and ethologists, urboecology, philosophers, anthropologists, art historians (V. G. Il’in, R. Park, L. Worth, E. Gorokhovskaya, I. A. Litvinova, V. I. Mathis, G. Simmel, E. Fromm, E. T. Hall, M. I. year-old boy, James W., Jean-Paul Ferrier, Jean-Albert Guieysse, Thierry Rebour, H. W. Zorbaugh, etc.). Used demographic statistics allowing to understand the issues of depopulation, migration and multi-ethnicity of the townspeople.Results and discussion. In modern culture hypertrophied original function of the city as a source of protection and comfort, it is a shift towards maximum convenience and independence of individuals. In the result, the urban environment is made, adapting to the challenges put forward by society. Historically “face” of the city gets lost. This jeopardizes not only the rich cultural heritage of the cities, but also the authenticity of the existence of the person. The ontological basis of the modern “concept” of the city is defined by urban characteristics: multiculturalism, multi-ethnicity, presentationhost (the image of the city), the superficiality of contact, the spontaneity of development, the blurring of boundaries. They not only make up the text of modern urban culture, but also form a macro model of society.Thus, the result of the study is the conceptualization of the contradictions of the modern city that provides for a person as comfortable as possible in the consumer environment at the same time directed against him or her.Conclusion. It is concluded that in the current ecological, demographic and economic situation, the question of understanding the role of modern urban culture in the search for a dialogue between the technogenic and informational development of civilization with nature, the historical and cultural content of the city with its image, and mass consumption with an original manifestation is most acute. The authors believe that it depends only on the person whether the urban space will exist for or against him or her.
- Published
- 2020
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
47. Legal Bases for the Interpretation of Contract Terms under the UNIDROIT Principles of International Commercial Contracts
- Author
-
Ho Kim, Chong-Seok Shim, and Bong-Chul Kim
- Subjects
Value (ethics) ,Order (business) ,Originality ,Interpretation (philosophy) ,media_common.quotation_subject ,Business ,Meaning (existential) ,Reasonable person ,Term (time) ,Contra proferentem ,Law and economics ,media_common - Abstract
Purpose – This paper examines the legal standards for the interpretation of contract terms in the UNIDROIT Principles of International Commercial Contracts (PICC) and the cases thereunder in order to provide academic implication to promoting an appropriate understanding of this topic in practical business. Design/methodology – This article uses the literature research and case study under the PICC. Findings – the contract terms shall be interpreted according to the common intention of the parties. If such an intention cannot be established, the contract shall be interpreted according to the meaning that reasonable persons of the same kind as the parties would give to it in the same circumstances. The statements and other conduct of a party shall be interpreted according to that party’s intention if the other party knew or could not have been unaware of that intention. If not, the reasonable person standard will apply. In applying above articles, all relevant circumstances including the conduct of the parties, practices and usages shall be considered. Terms and expressions shall be interpreted in the light of the whole contract or statement in which they appear and contract terms shall be interpreted so as to give effect to all the terms rather than to deprive some of them of effect. Where contract terms supplied by one party are unclear, contra proferentem rule applies. Where there is discrepancy between several equally authoritative versions of a contract, a preference is given to the interpretation according to the version originally drawn up. Where the parties to a contract have not agreed regarding an important term for their rights and duties, a term which is appropriate in the circumstances shall be supplied. Originality/value – This article examines various cases regarding the topic that were determined under the PICC. By finding legal standards and rulings of relevant cases, this article will help readers in practical business to enhance the ability to apply the provisions to their contracts.
- Published
- 2020
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
48. Medical Negligence Law in Australia
- Author
-
Roy G. Beran and John Devereux
- Subjects
Plaintiff ,media_common.quotation_subject ,Common law ,education ,Liability ,humanities ,Reasonable person ,Law ,Duty of care ,Position (finance) ,Causation ,Psychology ,Duty ,health care economics and organizations ,media_common - Abstract
Liability for medical negligence in Australia follows the common law pattern, viz a plaintiff needs to prove duty, breach, and causation of damage which is not too remote. Australian law distinguishes sharply between two aspects of a doctor’s duty. On the one hand, diagnosis and treatment is governed largely by a standard of what is widely accepted by peer professional opinion by a significant number of respected practitioners in the field, as competent professional practice. On the other hand, doctors have a duty to advise of material risks. A risk is material if a reasonable person, in the patient's position, if warned of the risk, would be likely to attach significance to it or if the medical practitioner is, or should be, reasonably aware that the particular patient, would do so.
- Published
- 2021
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
49. Rawlsian justice in healthcare: a response to Cox and Fritz
- Author
-
Abeezar I. Sarela
- Subjects
Health (social science) ,Health Policy ,Public policy ,06 humanities and the arts ,0603 philosophy, ethics and religion ,Economic Justice ,Reasonable person ,Contractualism ,03 medical and health sciences ,Issues, ethics and legal aspects ,Public law ,0302 clinical medicine ,Arts and Humanities (miscellaneous) ,Social Justice ,Humans ,060301 applied ethics ,030212 general & internal medicine ,Sociology ,Political philosophy ,Distributive justice ,Delivery of Health Care ,Public reason ,Law and economics - Abstract
Cox and Fritz state the central problem as the absence of a framework for healthcare policy decisions; but, they overlook the theoretical underpinnings of public law. In response, they propose a two-step procedure to guide fair decision-making. The first step relies on Thomas Scanlon’s ‘contractualism’ for stakeholders to consider whether, or not, they could reasonably reject policy proposals made by others; then in the second step, John Rawls’s principles of justice are applied to these proposals; a fair policy requires to pass both steps. I argue that Cox and Fritz misinterpret Rawls. His theory has two stages: first, public reason is used to generate principles of justice; second, public reason is used to interpret and apply these principles. The second stage requires that proposals are based on the principles of justice from the first stage, and these proposals have to be acceptable to reasonable persons. Thus, Rawls’s theory does not need Scanlonian supplementation. Moreover, the application of Rawls’s theory in Cox and Fritz’s model is confusing. In any case, the problems with applying Rawlsian justice to healthcare can be located elsewhere. First, Rawls’s theory would treat healthcare simply as a ‘primary good’ or resource. Social justice ought to, instead, consider healthcare as an opportunity, in the manner conceived by Amartya Sen. Second, Rawlsian justice rests, ultimately, on the conception of a reasonable person; until and unless the characteristics of reasonable stakeholders are clarified, any model of health justice will remain hostage to the unreasonable.
- Published
- 2021
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
50. No Reasonable Person
- Author
-
Taylor, George H., author, Jockers, Matthew L., author, and Nascimento, Fernando, author
- Published
- 2019
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
Catalog
Discovery Service for Jio Institute Digital Library
For full access to our library's resources, please sign in.