27 results on '"False Belief"'
Search Results
2. Mental files theory of mind: When do children consider agents acquainted with different object identities?
- Author
-
Huemer, Michael, Perner, Josef, and Leahy, Brian
- Subjects
- *
THEORY of mind , *CHILD psychology , *BELIEF & doubt , *TASK performance , *COGNITIVE neuroscience - Abstract
Mental files theory explains why children pass many perspective taking tasks like the false belief test around age 4 (Perner & Leahy, 2016). It also explains why older children struggle to understand that beliefs about an object depend on how one is acquainted with it (intensionality or aspectuality). If Heinz looks at an object that is both a die and an eraser, but cannot tell by looking that it is an eraser, he will not reach for it if he needs an eraser. Four- to 6-year olds find this difficult (Apperly & Robinson, 1998). We tested 129 35- to 86-month olds with a modified version of Apperly and Robinson's task. Each child faced four tasks resulting from two experimental factors, timing and mode of information. Timing: Children saw Heinz learn the die's location either before or after they learn that the die is an eraser. Mode of information: Heinz learns where the die is either perceptually or verbally. When Heinz' learning is verbal, he never perceives the die at all. We found that Apperly and Robinson's problem occurs only in the seen-after condition, where Heinz sees the die afterchildren had learnt that it was also an eraser. It vanishes when Heinz learns where the die is before children learn that it is also an eraser. The problem also vanishes when Heinz learns where the die is purely verbally (e.g., "The die is in the red box") and never sees it. This evidence lets us refine existing mental files theory, and eliminate several alternatives from the literature. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2018
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
3. Growing out of your own mind: Reexamining the development of the self-other difference in the unexpected contents task.
- Author
-
Sobel, David M.
- Subjects
- *
THEORY of mind , *LITERATURE reviews , *CHILD development - Abstract
The unexpected contents task is a well-established measure for studying young children's developing theory of mind. The task measures whether children understand that others have a false belief about a deceptive container and whether children can track the representational change in their own beliefs about the container's contents. Performance on both questions improves between the ages of 3 and 4. A previous meta-analysis (Wellman, Cross, & Watson, 2001) found little evidence for a difference in children's responses on these questions, but did not investigate the weak effect size that was reported for the interaction between age and question type. The two meta-analyses reported here update the literature review, and find a more robust interaction between question type and age. Three-year-olds showed better performance on questions about their own representational change than others' false belief, while older children showed the reverse pattern. A mega-analysis of a sample of over 1200 children between the ages of 36–60 months then showed the same result. This response pattern requires novel theoretical interpretations, which include reframing the development of children's understanding of false belief. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2023
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
4. Pragmatic development explains the Theory-of-Mind Scale.
- Author
-
Westra, Evan and Carruthers, Peter
- Subjects
- *
PHILOSOPHY of mind , *DISCOURSE markers , *NATIVISM (Psychology) , *HYPOTHESIS , *THOUGHT & thinking , *CHILD development , *CHILD psychology , *COGNITION , *SENSORY perception , *MATHEMATICAL models of psychology - Abstract
Henry Wellman and colleagues have provided evidence of a robust developmental progression in theory-of-mind (or as we will say, "mindreading") abilities, using verbal tasks. Understanding diverse desires is said to be easier than understanding diverse beliefs, which is easier than understanding that lack of perceptual access issues in ignorance, which is easier than understanding false belief, which is easier than understanding that people can hide their true emotions. These findings present a challenge to nativists about mindreading, and are said to support a social-constructivist account of mindreading development instead. This article takes up the challenge on behalf of nativism. Our goal is to show that the mindreading-scale findings fail to support constructivism because well-motivated alternative hypotheses have not yet been controlled for and ruled out. These have to do with the pragmatic demands of verbal tasks. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2017
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
5. The knowledge ("true belief") error in 4- to 6-year-old children: When are agents aware of what they have in view?
- Author
-
Huemer, Michael, Schröder, Lara M., Leikard, Sarah J., Gruber, Sara, Mangstl, Anna, and Perner, Josef
- Subjects
- *
THEORY of mind , *INTELLECT , *PROBLEM solving , *THOUGHT & thinking , *COGNITION - Abstract
The standard view on explicit theory of mind development holds that children around the age of 4 years start to ascribe beliefs to themselves and others, typically tested with false belief (FB) tasks. The present study (N = 95, 53 female, 41 male, Austrian, 41 to 80 months) systematically investigated the puzzling phenomenon that FB achievers (FB+) fail knowledge (often subsumed under "true belief") tasks: Despite the story protagonist witnessing the displacement of an object these children predict that the protagonist will look for it in its original location. We replicate this result in Experiment 1. Interestingly, some of our children indicated uncertainty about the protagonist's awareness of the relevant event. Thus, in Experiment 2 a new active watching condition was designed to help children understand that the protagonist attended to the critical event. This practically eradicated the knowledge error. Experiment 3 successfully replicated these results. Implications for existing explanations, perceptual access reasoning (PAR, Fabricius, Boyer, Weimer, & Carroll, 2010) and pragmatic difficulties (Oktay-Gür & Rakoczy, 2017) are discussed. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2023
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
6. Mental files and belief: A cognitive theory of how children represent belief and its intensionality.
- Author
-
Perner, Josef, Huemer, Michael, and Leahy, Brian
- Subjects
- *
CONTENT (Psychology) , *CHILD psychology , *MENTAL health , *COGNITIVE learning theory , *COGNITIVE analysis , *PSYCHOLOGY of belief & doubt , *PUPPET plays , *CHILD development , *COGNITION , *COMPARATIVE studies , *CONCEPTS , *CULTURE , *RESEARCH methodology , *MEDICAL cooperation , *PSYCHOLOGY , *RESEARCH , *RESEARCH funding , *THOUGHT & thinking , *THEORY , *EVALUATION research - Abstract
We provide a cognitive analysis of how children represent belief using mental files. We explain why children who pass the false belief test are not aware of the intensionality of belief. Fifty-one 3½- to 7-year old children were familiarized with a dual object, e.g., a ball that rattles and is described as a rattle. They observed how a puppet agent witnessed the ball being put into box 1. In the agent's absence the ball was taken from box 1, the child was reminded of it being a rattle, and emphasising its being a rattle it was put back into box 1. Then the agent returned, the object was hidden in the experimenter's hands and removed from box 1, described as a "rattle," and transferred to box 2. Children who passed false belief had no problem saying where the puppet would look for the ball. However, in a different condition in which the agent was also shown that the ball was a rattle they erroneously said that the agent would look for the ball in box 1, ignoring the agent's knowledge of the identity of rattle and ball. Their problems cease with their mastery of second-order beliefs (she thinks she knows). Problems also vanish when the ball is described not as a rattle but as a thing that rattles. We describe how our theory can account for these data as well as all other relevant data in the literature. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2015
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
7. Task constraints distinguish perspective inferences from perspective use during discourse interpretation in a false belief task.
- Author
-
Ferguson, Heather J., Apperly, Ian, Ahmad, Jumana, Bindemann, Markus, and Cane, James
- Subjects
- *
THOUGHT & thinking , *BELIEF & doubt , *TASK performance , *COGNITIVE ability , *EYE tracking - Abstract
Interpreting other peoples’ actions relies on an understanding of their current mental states (e.g. beliefs, desires and intentions). In this paper, we distinguish between listeners’ ability to infer others’ perspectives and their explicit use of this knowledge to predict subsequent actions. In a visual-world study, two groups of participants (passive observers vs . active participants) watched short videos, depicting transfer events, where one character (‘Jane’) either held a true or false belief about an object’s location. We tracked participants’ eye-movements around the final visual scene, time-locked to related auditory descriptions (e.g. “Jane will look for the chocolates in the container on the left”.). Results showed that active participants had already inferred the character’s belief in the 1 s preview period prior to auditory onset, before it was possible to use this information to predict an outcome. Moreover, they used this inference to correctly anticipate reference to the object’s initial location on false belief trials at the earliest possible point (i.e. from “Jane” onwards). In contrast, passive observers only showed evidence of a belief inference from the onset of “Jane”, and did not show reliable use of this inference to predict Jane’s behaviour on false belief trials until much later, when the location (“left/right”) was auditorily available. These results show that active engagement in a task activates earlier inferences about others’ perspectives, and drives immediate use of this information to anticipate others’ actions, compared to passive observers, who are susceptible to influences from egocentric or reality biases. Finally, we review evidence that using other peoples’ perspectives to predict their behaviour is more cognitively effortful than simply using one’s own. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2015
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
8. From self to social cognition: Theory of Mind mechanisms and their relation to Executive Functioning.
- Author
-
Bradford, Elisabeth E.F., Jentzsch, Ines, and Gomez, Juan-Carlos
- Subjects
- *
SOCIAL perception , *EXECUTIVE function , *THOUGHT & thinking , *MENTAL status examination , *COMPARATIVE studies , *BELIEF & doubt - Abstract
‘Theory of Mind’ refers to the ability to attribute mental states to oneself and other people (Premack & Woodruff, 1978). This study examined the extent to which ‘Self’ and ‘Other’ belief-attribution processes within the Theory of Mind (ToM) mechanism could be distinguished behaviourally, and whether these separable components differentially related to Executive Functioning (EF) abilities. A computerized false-belief task, utilizing a matched-design to allow direct comparison of self-oriented vs. other-oriented belief-attribution, was used to assess ToM, and a face-image Stroop task was employed to assess EF, within a population of typically-developed adults. Results revealed significantly longer reaction times when attributing beliefs to other people as opposed to recognizing and attributing beliefs to oneself. Intriguingly, results revealed that ‘perspective-shift’ requirements (i.e. changing from adoption of the ‘self’ perspective to the perspective of the ‘other’, or vice versa) across false-belief trials influenced reaction times. Reaction times were significantly longer when the perspective shift was from self-to-other than from other-to-self. It is suggested that the ‘self’ forms the stem of understanding the ‘other’, and is therefore processed regardless of ultimate task demands; in contrast, the ‘other’ perspective is only processed when explicitly required. We conclude that adopting another person’s perspective, even when their belief state is matched to one’s own, requires more cognitive effort than recalling and reflecting on self-oriented belief-states. [ABSTRACT FROM AUTHOR]
- Published
- 2015
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
9. The relationship between parental mental-state language and 2.5-year-olds’ performance on a nontraditional false-belief task
- Author
-
Rose M. Scott and Erin Roby
- Subjects
Male ,Parents ,Linguistics and Language ,Concept Formation ,Cognitive Neuroscience ,Culture ,Psychology of reasoning ,Experimental and Cognitive Psychology ,Language Development ,behavioral disciplines and activities ,050105 experimental psychology ,Language and Linguistics ,Developmental psychology ,Task (project management) ,Random Allocation ,Social cognition ,Developmental and Educational Psychology ,Humans ,0501 psychology and cognitive sciences ,Parent-Child Relations ,Association (psychology) ,False belief ,05 social sciences ,Anticipation, Psychological ,Child, Preschool ,Mental state ,Female ,Comprehension ,Psychology ,Photic Stimulation ,Psychomotor Performance ,050104 developmental & child psychology - Abstract
A growing body of evidence suggests that children succeed in nontraditional false-belief tasks in the first years of life. However, few studies have examined individual differences in infants' and toddlers' performance on these tasks. Here we investigated whether parental use of mental-state language (i.e. think, understand), which predicts children's performance on elicited-response false-belief tasks at older ages, also predicts toddlers' performance on a nontraditional task. We tested 2.5-year-old children in a verbal nontraditional false-belief task that included two looking time measures, anticipatory looking and preferential looking, and measured parents' use of mental-state language during a picture-book task. Parents' use of mental-state language positively predicted children's performance on the anticipatory-looking measure of the nontraditional task. These results provide the first evidence that social factors relate to children's false-belief understanding prior to age 3 and that this association extends to performance on nontraditional tasks. These findings add to a growing number of studies suggesting that mental-state language supports mental-state understanding across the lifespan.
- Published
- 2018
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
10. Children exhibit different performance patterns in explicit and implicit theory of mind tasks
- Author
-
Nese Oktay-Gür, Hannes Rakoczy, and Alexandra Schulz
- Subjects
Male ,Linguistics and Language ,Cognitive Neuroscience ,Theory of Mind ,Experimental and Cognitive Psychology ,050105 experimental psychology ,Language and Linguistics ,Thinking ,Child Development ,Theory of mind ,Developmental and Educational Psychology ,Humans ,0501 psychology and cognitive sciences ,Child ,Implicit personality theory ,Scope (project management) ,False belief ,05 social sciences ,Age Factors ,Cognition ,Social Perception ,Child, Preschool ,Female ,Psychology ,050104 developmental & child psychology ,Cognitive psychology - Abstract
Three studies tested scope and limits of children’s implicit and explicit theory of mind. In Studies 1 and 2, three- to six-year-olds (N = 84) were presented with closely matched explicit false belief tasks that differed in whether or not they required an understanding of aspectuality. Results revealed that children performed equally well in the different tasks, and performance was strongly correlated. Study 3 tested two-year-olds (N = 81) in implicit interactive versions of these tasks and found evidence for dis-unity: children performed competently only in those tasks that did not require an understanding of aspectuality. Taken together, the present findings suggest that early implicit and later explicit theory of mind tasks may tap different forms of cognitive capacities.
- Published
- 2018
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
11. Belief-based action prediction in preverbal infants.
- Author
-
Southgate, Victoria and Vernetti, Angelina
- Subjects
- *
BELIEF & doubt , *VERBAL ability in children , *MENTAL status examination , *SENSORIMOTOR cortex , *INFANT psychology , *NEURAL circuitry , *PHYSIOLOGY - Abstract
Highlights: [•] 6-month-olds consider others’ mental states when predicting their actions. [•] We use sensorimotor alpha suppression as a neural correlate of action prediction. [•] Infants predict an action only when the person’s belief should lead them to act. [Copyright &y& Elsevier]
- Published
- 2014
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
12. Eighteen-month-old infants show false belief understanding in an active helping paradigm
- Author
-
Buttelmann, David, Carpenter, Malinda, and Tomasello, Michael
- Subjects
- *
INFANT psychology , *SOCIAL perception , *BELIEF & doubt , *PARADIGM (Theory of knowledge) , *PHILOSOPHY of mind , *HELPING behavior in children , *GOAL (Psychology) , *BEHAVIORISM (Psychology) - Abstract
Abstract: Recently, several studies have claimed that soon after their first birthday infants understand others’ false beliefs. However, some have questioned these findings based on criticisms of the looking-time paradigms used. Here we report a new paradigm to test false belief understanding in infants using a more active behavioral response: helping. Specifically, the task was for infants to help an adult achieve his goal – but to determine that goal infants had to take into account what the adult believed (i.e., whether or not he falsely believed there was a toy inside a box). Results showed that by 18 months of age infants successfully took into account the adult’s belief in the process of attempting to determine his goal. Results for 16-month-olds were in the same direction but less clear. These results represent by far the youngest age of false belief understanding in a task with an active behavioral measure. [Copyright &y& Elsevier]
- Published
- 2009
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
13. Chimpanzees know what others know, but not what they believe
- Author
-
Kaminski, Juliane, Call, Josep, and Tomasello, Michael
- Subjects
- *
CHIMPANZEE psychology , *CHILD psychology , *COMPREHENSION , *IGNORANCE (Theory of knowledge) , *BELIEF & doubt , *SOCIAL perception - Abstract
Abstract: There is currently much controversy about which, if any, mental states chimpanzees and other nonhuman primates understand. In the current two studies we tested both chimpanzees’ and human children’s understanding of both knowledge–ignorance and false belief – in the same experimental paradigm involving competition with a conspecific. We found that whereas 6-year-old children understood both of these mental states, chimpanzees understood knowledge–ignorance but not false belief. After ruling out various alternative explanations of these and related findings, we conclude that in at least some situations chimpanzees know what others know. Possible explanations for their failure in the highly similar false belief task are discussed. [Copyright &y& Elsevier]
- Published
- 2008
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
14. Beyond Simulation–Theory and Theory–Theory: Why social cognitive neuroscience should use its own concepts to study “theory of mind”
- Author
-
Apperly, Ian A.
- Subjects
- *
THEORY (Philosophy) , *PHILOSOPHY of mind , *NEUROPSYCHOLOGY , *SOCIAL perception - Abstract
Abstract: The debate between Simulation–Theory (ST) and Theory–Theory (TT) provides the dominant theoretical framework for research on “theory of mind” (ToM). Behavioural research has failed to provide clear methods for discriminating between these theories, but a number of recent studies have claimed that neuroimaging methods do allow key predictions of ST and TT to be tested. In the current paper it is argued that neuroimaging studies have not in fact provided any data that discriminates between ST and TT accounts of propositional attitude ascription, and moreover that it is uncertain that they will in the future. However, it is also argued that the fault lies with the ST/TT debate, not with the methods and concepts of neuroimaging research. Neuroimaging can certainly contribute to our understanding of ToM, and should contribute to the project of developing theoretical models more firmly grounded in specific cognitive and neural processes than ST or TT. [Copyright &y& Elsevier]
- Published
- 2008
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
15. The cost of thinking about false beliefs: Evidence from adults’ performance on a non-inferential theory of mind task
- Author
-
Apperly, Ian A., Back, Elisa, Samson, Dana, and France, Lisa
- Subjects
- *
MANAGEMENT information systems , *INFORMATION storage & retrieval systems , *COMPUTER software , *ELECTRONIC data processing - Abstract
Abstract: Much of what we know about other people’s beliefs comes non-inferentially from what people tell us. Developmental research suggests that 3-year-olds have difficulty processing such information: they suffer interference from their own knowledge of reality when told about someone’s false belief (e.g., [Wellman, H. M., & Bartsch, K. (1988). Young children’s reasoning about beliefs. Cognition, 30, 239–277.]). The current studies examined for the first time whether similar interference occurs in adult participants. In two experiments participants read sentences describing the real colour of an object and a man’s false belief about the colour of the object, then judged the accuracy of a picture probe depicting either reality or the man’s belief. Processing costs for picture probes depicting reality were consistently greater in this false belief condition than in a matched control condition in which the sentences described the real colour of one object and a man’s unrelated belief about the colour of another object. A similar pattern was observed for picture probes depicting the man’s belief in most cases. Processing costs were not sensitive to the time available for encoding the information presented in the sentences: costs were observed when participants read the sentences at their own pace (Experiment 1) or at a faster or a slower pace (Experiment 2). This suggests that adults’ difficulty was not with encoding information about reality and a conflicting false belief, but with holding this information in mind and using it to inform a subsequent judgement. [Copyright &y& Elsevier]
- Published
- 2008
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
16. Testing the domain-specificity of a theory of mind deficit in brain-injured patients: Evidence for consistent performance on non-verbal, “reality-unknown” false belief and false photograph tasks
- Author
-
Apperly, Ian A., Samson, Dana, Chiavarino, Claudia, Bickerton, Wai-Ling, and Humphreys, Glyn W.
- Subjects
- *
BRAIN damaged patients , *BELIEF & doubt , *REASONING , *PSYCHOLOGICAL tests , *COGNITION disorders diagnosis , *BRAIN , *CEREBRAL dominance , *COGNITION disorders , *COMPARATIVE studies , *CULTURE , *NEUROPSYCHOLOGICAL tests , *RESEARCH methodology , *MEDICAL cooperation , *NONVERBAL communication , *SENSORY perception , *PSYCHOLOGY , *RESEARCH , *STROKE , *VISUAL perception , *THEORY , *EVALUATION research , *SEVERITY of illness index , *VIRAL encephalitis , *DISEASE complications - Abstract
Abstract: To test the domain-specificity of “theory of mind” abilities we compared the performance of a case-series of 11 brain-lesioned patients on a recently developed test of false belief reasoning () and on a matched false photograph task, which did not require belief reasoning and which addressed problems with existing false photograph methods. A strikingly similar pattern of performance was shown across the false belief and false photograph tests. Patients who were selectively impaired on false belief tasks were also impaired on false photograph tasks; patients spared on false belief tasks also showed preserved performance with false photographs. In some cases the impairment on false belief and false photograph tasks coincided with good performance on control tasks matched for executive demands. We discuss whether the patients have a domain-specific deficit in reasoning about representations common to both false belief and false photograph tasks. [Copyright &y& Elsevier]
- Published
- 2007
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
17. Mental files theory of mind: When do children consider agents acquainted with different object identities?
- Author
-
Huemer, Michael, Perner, Josef, and Leahy, Brian
- Subjects
Thinking ,Mental files ,Male ,Child Development ,Child, Preschool ,False belief ,Theory of Mind ,Humans ,Female ,Acquaintance ,Child ,Article ,Intensionality - Abstract
Mental files theory explains why children pass many perspective taking tasks like the false belief test around age 4 (Perner & Leahy, 2016). It also explains why older children struggle to understand that beliefs about an object depend on how one is acquainted with it (intensionality or aspectuality). If Heinz looks at an object that is both a die and an eraser, but cannot tell by looking that it is an eraser, he will not reach for it if he needs an eraser. Four- to 6-year olds find this difficult (Apperly & Robinson, 1998). We tested 129 35- to 86-month olds with a modified version of Apperly and Robinson’s task. Each child faced four tasks resulting from two experimental factors, timing and mode of information. Timing: Children saw Heinz learn the die’s location either before or after they learn that the die is an eraser. Mode of information: Heinz learns where the die is either perceptually or verbally. When Heinz’ learning is verbal, he never perceives the die at all. We found that Apperly and Robinson’s problem occurs only in the seen-after condition, where Heinz sees the die after children had learnt that it was also an eraser. It vanishes when Heinz learns where the die is before children learn that it is also an eraser. The problem also vanishes when Heinz learns where the die is purely verbally (e.g., “The die is in the red box”) and never sees it. This evidence lets us refine existing mental files theory, and eliminate several alternatives from the literature.
- Published
- 2017
18. Encoding of others’ beliefs without overt instruction
- Author
-
Adam S. Cohen and Tamsin C. German
- Subjects
Male ,Cognitive science ,Linguistics and Language ,Psychological science ,False belief ,Cognitive Neuroscience ,Automaticity ,Experimental and Cognitive Psychology ,Automatic processing ,Cognition ,Language and Linguistics ,Young Adult ,Mental Processes ,Social cognition ,Theory of mind ,Reaction Time ,Developmental and Educational Psychology ,Humans ,Female ,Cues ,Psychology ,Photic Stimulation ,Psychomotor Performance ,Cognitive psychology - Abstract
Under what conditions do people automatically encode and track the mental states of others? A recent investigation showed that when subjects are instructed to track the location of an object but are not instructed to track a belief about that location in a non-verbal false-belief task, they respond more slowly to questions about an agent’s belief, suggesting that belief information was not encoded or tracked automatically [Apperly, I. A., Riggs, K. J., Simpson, A., Samson, D., & Chiavarino, C. (2006). Is belief reasoning automatic? Psychological Science, 17, 841–844]. In the current experiments, we show that if belief probes occur closer in time to the events that signal the content of the agent’s false belief, responses to those probes are faster than responses to probes about reality, and as fast as responses to probes about belief when instructed to track them, suggesting (i) beliefs may get encoded automatically in response to certain cues and (ii) that belief information rapidly decays unless it is maintained via ‘top-down’ instructions.
- Published
- 2009
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
19. Can an agent’s false belief be corrected by an appropriate communication? Psychological reasoning in 18-month-old infants
- Author
-
Renée Baillargeon, Hyun Joo Song, Cynthia Fisher, and Kristine H. Onishi
- Subjects
Male ,Linguistics and Language ,genetic structures ,Experimental psychology ,Cognitive Neuroscience ,Psychology of reasoning ,Experimental and Cognitive Psychology ,Interpersonal communication ,Article ,Language and Linguistics ,Child Development ,Cognition ,Mental Processes ,Social cognition ,Developmental and Educational Psychology ,Humans ,False belief ,Communication ,Infant ,Comprehension ,Space Perception ,Ball (bearing) ,Female ,Psychology ,human activities ,Social psychology ,Cognitive psychology ,Gesture - Abstract
Do 18-month-olds understand that an agent's false belief can be corrected by an appropriate, though not an inappropriate, communication? In Experiment 1, infants watched a series of events involving two agents, a ball, and two containers: a box and a cup. To start, agent1 played with the ball and then hid it in the box, while agent2 looked on. Next, in agent1's absence, agent2 moved the ball from the box to the cup. When agent1 returned, agent2 told her "The ball is in the cup!" (informative-intervention condition) or "I like the cup!" (uninformative-intervention condition). During test, agent1 reached for either the box (box event) or the cup (cup event). In the informative-intervention condition, infants who saw the box event looked reliably longer than those who saw the cup event; in the uninformative-intervention condition, the reverse pattern was found. These results suggest that infants expected agent1's false belief about the ball's location to be corrected when she was told "The ball is in the cup!", but not "I like the cup!". In Experiment 2, agent2 simply pointed to the ball's new location, and infants again expected agent1's false belief to be corrected. These and control results provide additional evidence that infants in the second year of life can attribute false beliefs to agents. In addition, the results suggest that by 18 months of age infants expect agents' false beliefs to be corrected by relevant communications involving words or gestures.
- Published
- 2008
- Full Text
- View/download PDF
20. Mirrors, mirrors on the wall…the ubiquitous multiple reflection error
- Author
-
Rebecca Lawson
- Subjects
Male ,Linguistics and Language ,Communication ,business.industry ,False belief ,Cognitive Neuroscience ,Experimental and Cognitive Psychology ,Recognition, Psychology ,Language and Linguistics ,Young Adult ,Optics ,Pattern Recognition, Visual ,Orientation ,Developmental and Educational Psychology ,Visual Perception ,Humans ,Female ,business ,Set (psychology) ,Reflection (computer graphics) ,Psychology ,Photic Stimulation ,Psychomotor Performance - Abstract
Participants decided when somebody, Janine, could see their face in a horizontal row of adjacent mirrors mounted flat on the same wall. They saw real mirrors and a shop-dummy representing Janine. Such coplanar mirrors reflect different, non-overlapping areas of a scene. However, almost everybody made an unexpected error: they claimed that Janine would see her face reflected in multiple mirrors simultaneously. They therefore responded as if each mirror showed similar information and thus grossly overestimated how much each mirror revealed. Further studies established that this multiple reflection error also occurred for vertical rows of mirrors and for different areas of a single, large mirror. The error was even common if the participant themselves sat in front of a set of covered-up mirrors and indicated where they would be able to see their own reflection. In the latter case, people often made multiple reflection errors despite having seen all the mirrors uncovered immediately before they responded. People’s gross overestimation of how much of a scene a mirror reflects and their inability to learn to correct this false belief explains why, despite a lifetime’s experience of mirrors, they incorrectly think they will see themselves in all nearby mirrors.
- Published
- 2011
21. A constructivist connectionist model of transitions on false-belief tasks
- Author
-
Kristine H. Onishi, Thomas R. Shultz, and Vincent G. Berthiaume
- Subjects
Linguistics and Language ,Cognitive Neuroscience ,Culture ,Theory of Mind ,Experimental and Cognitive Psychology ,Models, Psychological ,Language and Linguistics ,Child Development ,Cognition ,Connectionism ,Theory of mind ,Developmental and Educational Psychology ,Cognitive development ,Humans ,Child ,Cognitive science ,Computational model ,False belief ,Object (philosophy) ,Social Perception ,Child, Preschool ,Mental representation ,Neural Networks, Computer ,Attribution ,Psychology ,Cognitive psychology - Abstract
How do children come to understand that others have mental representations, e.g., of an object’s location? Preschoolers go through two transitions on verbal false-belief tasks, in which they have to predict where an agent will search for an object that was moved in her absence. First, while three-and-a-half-year-olds usually fail at approach tasks, in which the agent wants to find the object, children just under four succeed. Second, only after four do children succeed at tasks in which the agent wants to avoid the object. We present a constructivist connectionist model that autonomously reproduces the two transitions and suggests that the transitions are due to increases in general processing abilities enabling children to (1) overcome a default true-belief attribution by distinguishing false- from true-belief situations, and to (2) predict search in avoidance situations, where there is often more than one correct, empty search location. Constructivist connectionist models are rigorous, flexible and powerful tools that can be analyzed before and after transitions to uncover novel and emergent mechanisms of cognitive development.
- Published
- 2009
22. Chimpanzees know what others know, but not what they believe
- Author
-
Josep Call, Juliane Kaminski, and Michael Tomasello
- Subjects
Adult ,Male ,Linguistics and Language ,Pan troglodytes ,False belief ,Cognitive Neuroscience ,Reproducibility of Results ,Experimental and Cognitive Psychology ,Cognition ,Language and Linguistics ,Developmental psychology ,Comprehension ,Knowledge ,Mental Processes ,Social cognition ,Theory of mind ,Developmental and Educational Psychology ,Cognitive development ,Animals ,Humans ,Female ,Psychology ,Child - Abstract
There is currently much controversy about which, if any, mental states chimpanzees and other nonhuman primates understand. In the current two studies we tested both chimpanzees’ and human children’s understanding of both knowledge–ignorance and false belief – in the same experimental paradigm involving competition with a conspecific. We found that whereas 6-year-old children understood both of these mental states, chimpanzees understood knowledge–ignorance but not false belief. After ruling out various alternative explanations of these and related findings, we conclude that in at least some situations chimpanzees know what others know. Possible explanations for their failure in the highly similar false belief task are discussed.
- Published
- 2007
23. Two reasons to abandon the false belief task as a test of theory of mind
- Author
-
Tim P. German and Paul Bloom
- Subjects
Linguistics and Language ,Pan troglodytes ,Logic ,Cognitive Neuroscience ,Concept Formation ,Experimental and Cognitive Psychology ,Language and Linguistics ,Task (project management) ,Concept learning ,Theory of mind ,Developmental and Educational Psychology ,Cognitive development ,Animals ,Humans ,Child ,Problem Solving ,False belief ,Social perception ,Infant ,Cognition ,Object Attachment ,Test (assessment) ,Social Perception ,Child, Preschool ,Psychology ,Social psychology ,Cognitive psychology - Abstract
The false belief task has often been used as a test of theory of mind. We present two reasons to abandon this practice. First, passing the false belief task requires abilities other than theory of mind. Second, theory of mind need not entail the ability to reason about false beliefs. We conclude with an alternative conception of the role of the false belief task.
- Published
- 2000
24. Three- and four-year-old children's ability to use desire- and belief-based reasoning
- Author
-
Kimberly Wright Cassidy
- Subjects
Linguistics and Language ,Deception ,Logic ,Cognitive Neuroscience ,Culture ,Experimental and Cognitive Psychology ,Psychology, Child ,Thinking skills ,Language and Linguistics ,Developmental psychology ,Child Development ,Theory of mind ,Developmental and Educational Psychology ,Cognitive development ,Humans ,Problem Solving ,Preschool child ,Motivation ,Age differences ,False belief ,Information processing ,Cognition ,Social Perception ,Child, Preschool ,Psychology ,Cognitive psychology - Abstract
Recently, several researchers have claimed that young 3-year-old children rely on desire when making behavioral predictions and that this causes poor performance on standard measures of false-belief understanding. This study investigates this claim. Results suggest that young children may, in fact, be using desire to predict behavior in these standard paradigms. Importantly, it is the desires of the agent, not the child's own desires that are used to make the prediction. Further, older preschool children also have some difficulty coordinating both belief and desire when processing demands are increased.
- Published
- 1998
25. Contamination in reasoning about false belief: an instance of realist bias in adults but not children
- Author
-
Peter Mitchell, Rebecca Nye, J.E. Isaacs, and Elizabeth J. Robinson
- Subjects
Male ,Linguistics and Language ,Intellectual development ,Adolescent ,Cognitive Neuroscience ,Prior learning ,Experimental and Cognitive Psychology ,Thinking skills ,Language and Linguistics ,Developmental psychology ,Judgment ,Cognition ,Theory of mind ,Developmental and Educational Psychology ,Cognitive development ,Humans ,Child ,Problem Solving ,False belief ,humanities ,Cognitive bias ,Child, Preschool ,Female ,Psychology ,Social psychology ,psychological phenomena and processes - Abstract
Children aged around 5 and 9 years and adults were presented with stories and videos about a protagonist who heard a message purporting to provide factual information. Observing subjects knew whether the message was true or false. In some cases, this message contradicted the listener's existing belief based on what he or she had seen previously. Subjects judged whether the listener would believe or disbelieve the message. Child subjects frequently judged that a contradicting message would be disbelieved, irrespective of whether they (the child subjects) knew it to be true or false. In contrast, adult subjects made judgements that were contaminated by their own privileged knowledge of the truth. For three different scenarios, adult subjects judged more frequently that the message would be believed if they (but not the listener protagonist) knew it to be true, than if they thought it was false.
- Published
- 1996
26. [Untitled]
- Subjects
Linguistics and Language ,False belief ,Cognitive Neuroscience ,05 social sciences ,Experimental and Cognitive Psychology ,Object (philosophy) ,050105 experimental psychology ,Language and Linguistics ,Test (assessment) ,Task (project management) ,Mode (computer interface) ,Theory of mind ,Perspective-taking ,Developmental and Educational Psychology ,0501 psychology and cognitive sciences ,Psychology ,050104 developmental & child psychology ,Cognitive psychology - Abstract
Mental files theory explains why children pass many perspective taking tasks like the false belief test around age 4 (Perner & Leahy, 2016). It also explains why older children struggle to understand that beliefs about an object depend on how one is acquainted with it (intensionality or aspectuality). If Heinz looks at an object that is both a die and an eraser, but cannot tell by looking that it is an eraser, he will not reach for it if he needs an eraser. Four- to 6-year olds find this difficult (Apperly & Robinson, 1998). We tested 129 35- to 86-month olds with a modified version of Apperly and Robinson’s task. Each child faced four tasks resulting from two experimental factors, timing and mode of information. Timing: Children saw Heinz learn the die’s location either before or after they learn that the die is an eraser. Mode of information: Heinz learns where the die is either perceptually or verbally. When Heinz’ learning is verbal, he never perceives the die at all. We found that Apperly and Robinson’s problem occurs only in the seen-after condition, where Heinz sees the die after children had learnt that it was also an eraser. It vanishes when Heinz learns where the die is before children learn that it is also an eraser. The problem also vanishes when Heinz learns where the die is purely verbally (e.g., “The die is in the red box”) and never sees it. This evidence lets us refine existing mental files theory, and eliminate several alternatives from the literature.
27. [Untitled]
- Subjects
Cognitive science ,Linguistics and Language ,False belief ,Cognitive Neuroscience ,05 social sciences ,Concept development ,Cognitive analysis ,Experimental and Cognitive Psychology ,Cognition ,050105 experimental psychology ,Language and Linguistics ,Theory of mind ,Developmental and Educational Psychology ,Ball (bearing) ,0501 psychology and cognitive sciences ,Psychology ,050104 developmental & child psychology ,Cognitive psychology - Abstract
We provide a cognitive analysis of how children represent belief using mental files. We explain why children who pass the false belief test are not aware of the intensionality of belief. Fifty-one 3½- to 7-year old children were familiarized with a dual object, e.g., a ball that rattles and is described as a rattle. They observed how a puppet agent witnessed the ball being put into box 1. In the agent's absence the ball was taken from box 1, the child was reminded of it being a rattle, and emphasising its being a rattle it was put back into box 1. Then the agent returned, the object was hidden in the experimenter's hands and removed from box 1, described as a "rattle," and transferred to box 2. Children who passed false belief had no problem saying where the puppet would look for the ball. However, in a different condition in which the agent was also shown that the ball was a rattle they erroneously said that the agent would look for the ball in box 1, ignoring the agent's knowledge of the identity of rattle and ball. Their problems cease with their mastery of second-order beliefs (she thinks she knows). Problems also vanish when the ball is described not as a rattle but as a thing that rattles. We describe how our theory can account for these data as well as all other relevant data in the literature.
Catalog
Discovery Service for Jio Institute Digital Library
For full access to our library's resources, please sign in.